Results for 'Egocentric space'

997 found
Order:
  1. The structure of egocentric space.Adrian J. T. Alsmith - 2020 - In Frédérique de Vignemont (ed.), The World at Our Fingertips: A Multidisciplinary Exploration of Peripersonal Space. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    This chapter offers an indirect defence of the Evansian conception of egocentric space, by showing how it resolves a puzzle concerning the unity of egocentric spatial perception. The chapter outlines several common assumptions about egocentric perspectival structure and argues that a subject’s experience, both within and across her sensory modalities, may involve multiple structures of this kind. This raises the question of how perspectival unity is achieved, such that these perspectival structures form a complex whole, rather (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2. Egocentric Space.Joel Smith - 2014 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (3):409-433.
    I discuss the relation between egocentric spatial representation and the capacity for bodily activity, with specific reference to Merleau-Ponty.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3.  44
    The representation of egocentric space in the posterior parietal cortex.J. F. Stein - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):691-700.
    The posterior parietal cortex (PPC) is the most likely site where egocentric spatial relationships are represented in the brain. PPC cells receive visual, auditory, somaesthetic, and vestibular sensory inputs; oculomotor, head, limb, and body motor signals; and strong motivational projections from the limbic system. Their discharge increases not only when an animal moves towards a sensory target, but also when it directs its attention to it. PPC lesions have the opposite effect: sensory inattention and neglect. The PPC does not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  4. Exocentric directions in egocentric space.J. J. Koenderink, A. J. van Doorn & J. S. Lappin - 1996 - In Enrique Villanueva (ed.), Perception. Ridgeview. pp. 62-62.
  5.  23
    Stimulus location in egocentric space as a determinant of apparent visual size.Leonard Brosgole & Hanan Yaniv - 1985 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 23 (6):477-478.
  6.  33
    Dynamic size perception as a function of target location in egocentric space.Leonard Brosgole - 1993 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 31 (4):282-284.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Space in the brain: Different neural substrates for allocentric and egocentric frames of reference.Melvyn A. Goodale & K. Murphy - 2000 - In Thomas Metzinger (ed.), Neural Correlates of Consciousness. MIT Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. Egocentric Spatial Representation in Action and Perception.Robert Briscoe - 2009 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79 (2):423-460.
    Neuropsychological findings used to motivate the "two visual systems" hypothesis have been taken to endanger a pair of widely accepted claims about spatial representation in conscious visual experience. The first is the claim that visual experience represents 3-D space around the perceiver using an egocentric frame of reference. The second is the claim that there is a constitutive link between the spatial contents of visual experience and the perceiver's bodily actions. In this paper, I review and assess three (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  9.  48
    Evidence for the embodiment of space perception: concurrent hand but not arm action moderates reachability and egocentric distance perception.Stéphane Grade, Mauro Pesenti & Martin G. Edwards - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10. Spatial memory: how egocentric and allocentric combine.Neil Burgess - 2006 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 10 (12):551-557.
  11.  15
    Space in Hand and Mind: Gesture and Spatial Frames of Reference in Bilingual Mexico.Tyler Marghetis, Melanie McComsey & Kensy Cooperrider - 2020 - Cognitive Science 44 (12):e12920.
    Speakers of many languages prefer allocentric frames of reference (FoRs) when talking about small‐scale space, using words like “east” or “downhill.” Ethnographic work has suggested that this preference is also reflected in how such speakers gesture. Here, we investigate this possibility with a field experiment in Juchitán, Mexico. In Juchitán, a preferentially allocentric language (Isthmus Zapotec) coexists with a preferentially egocentric one (Spanish). Using a novel task, we elicited spontaneous co‐speech gestures about small‐scale motion events (e.g., toppling blocks) (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  97
    Representing space in language and perception.David J. Bryant - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (3-4):239-264.
    Space can be understood through perception and language, but are the processes that represent spatial information the same in both cases? This paper reviews psychological evidence for the functional equivalence of spatial representations based on perceptual and linguistic inputs. It is proposed that spatial information is processed by a specialised spatial representation system (SRS) that creates geometric representations of space. The SRS receives inputs from perceptual and linguistic systems and uses these basic inputs to construct mental spatial models (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  13. Space, self, and the theater of consciousness.Arnold Trehub - 2007 - Consciousness and Cognition 16 (2):310-330.
    Over a decade ago, I introduced a large-scale theory of the cognitive brain which explained for the first time how the human brain is able to create internal models of its intimate world and invent models of a wider universe. An essential part of the theoretical model is an organization of neuronal mechanisms which I have named the Retinoid Model (Trehub, 1977, 1991). This hypothesized brain system has structural and dynamic properties enabling it to register and appropriately integrate disparate foveal (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  14.  15
    Representing Space in Language and Perception.David J. Bryant - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (3-4):239-264.
    Space can be understood through perception and language, but are the processes that represent spatial information the same in both cases? This paper reviews psychological evidence for the functional equivalence of spatial representations based on perceptual and linguistic inputs. It is proposed that spatial information is processed by a specialised spatial representation system (SRS) that creates geometric representations of space. The SRS receives inputs from perceptual and linguistic systems and uses these basic inputs to construct mental spatial models (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15. Self, world and space: The meaning and mechanisms of ego- and allocentric spatial representation.Rick Grush - 2000 - Brain and Mind 1 (1):59-92.
    b>: The problem of how physical systems, such as brains, come to represent themselves as subjects in an objective world is addressed. I develop an account of the requirements for this ability that draws on and refines work in a philosophical tradition that runs from Kant through Peter Strawson to Gareth Evans. The basic idea is that the ability to represent oneself as a subject in a world whose existence is independent of oneself involves the ability to represent space, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  16. Space and Self-Awareness.John Louis Schwenkler - 2009 - Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley
    How should we think about the role of visual spatial awareness in perception and perceptual knowledge? A common view, which finds a characteristic expression in Kant but has an intellectual heritage reaching back farther than that, is that an account of spatial awareness is fundamental to a theory of experience because spatiality is the defining characteristic of “outer sense”, of our perceptual awareness of how things are in the parts of the world that surround us. A natural counterpart to this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  48
    Phenomenal space and the unity of conscious experience.Douglas B. Meehan - 2003 - PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 9.
    One's contemporaneous conscious mental states seem bound in a single, unified experience. Dainton argues, against what he calls the S-Thesis, that we cannot explain such co-consciousness in terms of states' being located in a single phenomenal space, a functional space posited to explain our ability to locate ourselves relative to perceived stimuli. But Dainton's argument rests on a conflation of egocentric and allocentric self-localizing, and thus fails to undermine the S-Thesis. Nevertheless, experiments on visual neglect suggest one (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Action, see Interpreting human action Age trends, 64 harm versus intention, 65 Altruism. 430-434 rescuers, 440-442.Sociomoral Competence Scales & Piaget Egocentrism - 1991 - In William M. Kurtines & Jacob L. Gewirtz (eds.), Handbook of Moral Behavior and Development. L. Erlbaum. pp. 459.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Vision for Action and the Contents of Perception.Berit Brogaard - 2012 - Journal of Philosophy 109 (10):569-587.
    This paper examines Milner and Goodale’s hypothesis about the two visual streams and raises the questions of whether properties in egocentric space (commonly associated with the vision-for-action, or "dorsal," stream) can be part of the phenomenal content of perceptual experience, or only properties in allocentric space (commonly associated with the vision-for-perception, or "ventral," stream) can play this role, and how (if at all) properties in egocentric space differ from properties in allocentric space. These questions (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  20. Elisabetta ladavas and Alessandro farne.Representations Of Space & Near Specific Body Parts - 2004 - In Charles Spence & Jon Driver (eds.), Crossmodal Space and Crossmodal Attention. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Part XI: Flesh, Body, Embodiment.Space & Time - 2018 - In Daniela Verducci, Jadwiga Smith & William Smith (eds.), Eco-Phenomenology: Life, Human Life, Post-Human Life in the Harmony of the Cosmos. Cham: Springer Verlag.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. William G. Lycan.Logical Space & New Directions In Semantics - 1987 - In Ernest LePore (ed.), New directions in semantics. Orlando: Academic Press. pp. 143.
  23. International and National Symposia, Courses and Meetings.Space Occupying - forthcoming - Laguna.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  31
    Email: Tmuel 1 er@ F dm. uni-f reiburg. De.Branching Space-Time & Modal Logic - 2002 - In T. Placek & J. Butterfield (eds.), Non-Locality and Modality. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 273.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  38
    Hgikj.Farewell Minkowski Space - 1997 - Apeiron 4 (1):33.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Hoboken.Discovery Space - 1994 - Science Education 78 (2):137-148.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  11
    Leszek Wronski.Branching Space-Times - 2013 - In Hanne Andersen, Dennis Dieks, Wenceslao González, Thomas Uebel & Gregory Wheeler (eds.), New Challenges to Philosophy of Science. Springer Verlag. pp. 135.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  11
    Nuel Belnap.of Branching Space-Times - 2002 - In T. Placek & J. Butterfield (eds.), Non-Locality and Modality. Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  21
    gay (ze) doesn't reciprocate'the look', rather a lesbian reading is imposed upon her, more in hope than anticipation. But the voyeur can still momentarily imagine the space as her own, producing a small fissure in hegemonic hetero-sexual space. Lesbian spaces are also mobilized through linguistic structures of meaning. [REVIEW]Lesbian Productions Of Space - 1996 - In Nancy Duncan (ed.), BodySpace: destabilizing geographies of gender and sexuality. New York: Routledge.
  30.  59
    Schizophrenia: First you see it; then you don't.Rue L. Cromwell & Lawrence G. Space - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):597-598.
  31.  15
    When inspiration strikes, don't bottle it up! Write to me at: Philosophy Now 43a Jerningham Road• London• SE14 5NQ, UK or email rick. lewis@ philosophynow. org Keep them short and keep them coming! [REVIEW]Outta Space - forthcoming - Philosophy Now.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Bodily awareness and novel multisensory features.Robert Eamon Briscoe - 2021 - Synthese 198:3913-3941.
    According to the decomposition thesis, perceptual experiences resolve without remainder into their different modality-specific components. Contrary to this view, I argue that certain cases of multisensory integration give rise to experiences representing features of a novel type. Through the coordinated use of bodily awareness—understood here as encompassing both proprioception and kinaesthesis—and the exteroceptive sensory modalities, one becomes perceptually responsive to spatial features whose instances couldn’t be represented by any of the contributing modalities functioning in isolation. I develop an argument for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  33. Sarah Keenan.A. Prison Around Your Ankle, Space A. Border in Every Street : Theorising Law & The Subject - 2018 - In Andreas Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos (ed.), Routledge Handbook of Law and Theory. New York, NY: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  8
    Index to Volume 60.Jonathan Duquette, K. Ramasubramanian & Is Space Created - 2010 - Philosophy East and West 60 (4):567-570.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Vigier III.Spin Foam Spinors & Fundamental Space-Time Geometry - 2000 - Foundations of Physics 30 (1).
  36.  68
    Navigation bicoded as functions of x-y and time?James G. Phillips & Rowan P. Ogeil - 2013 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (5):561-562.
    Evidence from egocentric space is cited to support bicoding of navigation in three-dimensional space. Horizontal distances and space are processed differently from the vertical. Indeed, effector systems are compatible in horizontal space, but potentially incompatible (or chaotic) during transitions to vertical motion. Navigation involves changes in coordinates, and animal models of navigation indicate that time has an important role.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. The self as an embedded agent.Chris Dobbyn & Susan A. J. Stuart - 2003 - Minds and Machines 13 (2):187-201.
    In this paper we consider the concept of a self-aware agent. In cognitive science agents are seen as embodied and interactively situated in worlds. We analyse the meanings attached to these terms in cognitive science and robotics, proposing a set of conditions for situatedness and embodiment, and examine the claim that internal representational schemas are largely unnecessary for intelligent behaviour in animats. We maintain that current situated and embodied animats cannot be ascribed even minimal self-awareness, and offer a six point (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  38.  35
    where Am I? Redux.Arnold Trehub - 2013 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 20 (1-2):207 -225.
    Activation of the brainʼs putative retinoid system has been proposed as the neuronal substrate for our basic sense of being centered within a volumetric surround –- our minimal phenomenal consciousness (Trehub 2007). Here, the assumed properties of the self-locus within the retinoid model are shown to explain recent experimental findings relating to the out-of-body-experience. In addition, selective excursion of the heuristic self-locus is able to explain many important functions of consciousness, including the effective internal representation of a 3D space (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39. Mental imagery and the varieties of amodal perception.Robert Eamon Briscoe - 2011 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 92 (2):153-173.
    The problem of amodal perception is the problem of how we represent features of perceived objects that are occluded or otherwise hidden from us. Bence Nanay (2010) has recently proposed that we amodally perceive an object's occluded features by imaginatively projecting them into the relevant regions of visual egocentric space. In this paper, I argue that amodal perception is not a single, unitary capacity. Drawing appropriate distinctions reveals amodal perception to be characterized not only by mental imagery, as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  40. Transparency and sensorimotor contingencies: Do we see through photographs?Bence Nanay - 2010 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 91 (4):463-480.
    It has been claimed that photographs are transparent: we see through them; we literally see the photographed object through the photograph. Whether this claim is true depends on the way we conceive of seeing. There has been a controversy about whether localizing the perceived object in one's egocentric space is a necessary feature of seeing, as if it is, then photographs are unlikely to be transparent. I would like to propose and defend another, much weaker, necessary condition for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  41.  14
    Neurobiological Underpinnings of the Projection of Conscious Contents.Alfredo Pereira - 2023 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 30 (1):21-42.
    The projection of conscious content is a central feature of Max Velmans' theory of consciousness, implying that conscious experiences are built within a conversation of minds and worlds in which they form a 'reflexive' unity – as stated in his reflexive monism theory. What are the neurobiological structures and functions that underpin the experience of conscious contents being located in a spatio-temporal frame outside the nervous system that instantiates them? In this paper I offer informed speculation about these neurobiological structures (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  4
    Index.James R. Hamilton - 2007 - In The Art of Theater. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 222–226.
    This chapter contains section titled: Identifying Characters, Events, and Other Objects in Narrative Performances Re‐Identification of Characters and Other Objects in Narrative Performances The Special Nature of Theatrical (Uses of) Space: Performances and Performance Space Cross‐Performance Re‐Identification Identifying and Re‐Identifying Objects in Non‐Narrative Performances Added Benefits of the Demonstrative and Recognition based Approach to Identification and Re‐Identification Theatrical Performance as a Fully Independent Practice.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Unilateral neglect and the objectivity of spatial representation.Bill Brewer - 1992 - Mind and Language 7 (3):222-39.
    Patients may show a more-or-less complete deviation of the head and eyes towards the right (ipsilesional) side [that is, to the same side of egocentric space as the brain lesion responsible for their disorder]. If addressed by the examiner from the left (contralesional) side [the opposite side to their lesion], patients with severe extrapersonal neglect may fail to respond or may look for the speaker in the right side of the room, turning head and eyes more and more (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44. Identidad y discriminación en el contenido no conceptual.Justina Díaz Legaspe - 2009 - Critica 41 (123):65-93.
    En The Varieties of Reference, Evans sostiene que el contenido perceptual posee una naturaleza no conceptual. Precisamente, los vínculos informacionales entre sujeto y objeto habilitan el pensamiento singular, al permitir la localización del objeto en un entorno egocéntrico. Anclados en algunos casos en estos vínculos, los pensamientos singulares contienen Ideas adecuadas del objeto, dependientes de una determinada clasificación del mismo. Nada en el contenido perceptual equivale a este recorte conceptual del objeto en el pensamiento. Sostendré entonces la necesidad de introducir (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  58
    Explaining “spatial purport of perception”: a predictive processing approach.Wiktor Rorot - 2020 - Synthese 198 (10):9739-9762.
    Despite the large interest in the human ability to perceive space present in neuroscience, cognitive science and psychology, as well as philosophy of mind, the issues regarding egocentric space representation received relatively less attention. In this paper I take up a unique phenomenon related to this faculty: the “spatial purport” of perceptual experiences. The notion was proposed by Rick Grush to describe the subjective, qualitative aspects of egocentric representations of spatial properties and relations. Although Grush offered (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  13
    Curriculum and the cultivation of critical thinking: A critical realist conception.Shi Pu & Hao Xu - forthcoming - Educational Philosophy and Theory.
    In this article, we offer a critical realist conception of curriculum that aims to cultivate critical thinking (CT) and liberate students from egocentric rationality. We first examine egocentric rationality as a problem emerging from the technicist paradigm of cultivating CT in higher education, exemplified by issues arising from the pedagogical activity of debate. We then examine existing approaches to cultivating CT, focusing on the extent to which their goals and conceptions of CT could liberate students from egocentric (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. A mechanism for spatial perception on human skin.Francesca Fardo, Brianna Beck, Tony Cheng & Patrick Haggard - 2018 - Cognition 178 (C):236-243.
    Our perception of where touch occurs on our skin shapes our interactions with the world. Most accounts of cutaneous localisation emphasise spatial transformations from a skin-based reference frame into body-centred and external egocentric coordinates. We investigated another possible method of tactile localisation based on an intrinsic perception of ‘skin space’. The arrangement of cutaneous receptive fields (RFs) could allow one to track a stimulus as it moves across the skin, similarly to the way animals navigate using path integration. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  48. Der Nullpunkt der Orientierung.Geert Keil - 2002 - In Audun Øfsti, Peter Ulrich & Truls Wyller (eds.), Indexicality and Idealism: The Self in Philosophical Perspective. Mentis. pp. 9-29.
    The indexical sentence “I am here now” can be used any time and anywhere by anyone to say something true. Rather than yielding a special kind of infallible knowledge, this fact indicates that every speaker or thinker has a zero of an egocentric coordinate system at his disposal. Many idealist philosophers assume that this egocentric zero can be further reduced. The ability to make a de se-reference with the first person pronoun, they claim, need not involve spatiotemporal self-localization. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  16
    Mapping Utopias: A Voyage to Placelessness.Andreas Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos - 2001 - Law and Critique 12 (2):135-157.
    I have a map which indicates clearly and beyond any doubt the way to Utopia. I start the journey with a survival kit of paradigmatic egalities, noumenal legalities, and nervous ideals. However, the more I move into the uncartographied space, the more I realise that my survival kit is changing, to the point of becoming porous and permeable. The journey to Utopia is condensed to a log of phenomenological bracketing, where the immersion to the Lebensweltequals the loss of oneself, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50.  35
    Husserl’s Lebenswelt and the problem of spatial cognition – in search of universals.Elżbieta Łukasiewicz - 2010 - Polish Journal of Philosophy 4 (1):23-43.
    Perception and conceptualization of space are some of the most basic elements of human cognition. It has been long assumed that human spatial thinkingand frames of reference used to grasp and describe the location of an object in relation to other objects are of universal nature and so are projected in naturallanguages in basically the same manner; three principal dimensions in egocentric perceptual space were distinguished: up-down, front-back and left-right, reflecting our biological make-up. If differences in spatial (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 997