Results for 'chess analogy'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Language and chess: De saussure's analogy.Maurice Mandelbaum - 1968 - Philosophical Review 77 (3):356-357.
  2. Scorekeeping in a chess game.Bryan Pickel & Brian Rabern - 2022 - Semantics and Pragmatics 15 (12).
    There is an important analogy between languages and games. Just as a scoresheet records features of the evolution of a game to determine the effect of a move in that game, a conversational score records features of the evolution of a conversation to determine the effect of the linguistic moves that speakers make. Chess is particularly interesting for the study of conversational dynamics because it has language-like notations, and so serves as a simplified study in how the effect (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  42
    Chess, Games, and Flies.Stefano Franchi - 2005 - Essays in Philosophy 6 (1):85-114.
    Research in Artificial Intelligence has always had a very strong relationship with games and game-playing, and especially with chess. Workers in AI have always denied that this interest was more than purely accidental. Parlor games, they claimed, became a favorite topic of interest because they provided the ideal test case for any simulation of intelligence. Chess is the Drosophila of AI, it was said, with reference to the fruit-fly whose fast reproductive cycle made it into a favorite test (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  88
    Philosophy Looks at Chess.Benjamin Hale (ed.) - 2008 - Open Court Press.
    This book offers a collection of contemporary essays that explore philosophical themes at work in chess. This collection includes essays on the nature of a game, the appropriateness of chess as a metaphor for life, and even deigns to query whether Garry Kasparov might—just might—be a cyborg. In twelve unique essays, contributed by philosophers with a broad range of expertise in chess, this book poses both serious and playful questions about this centuries-old pastime. -/- Perhaps more interestingly, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  33
    They Do What They Are Told to Do: The Influence of Instruction on (Chess) Expert Perception—Commentary on Linhares and Brum (2007).Merim Bilalić & Fernand Gobet - 2009 - Cognitive Science 33 (5):743-747.
    Linhares and Brum (2007) argue that they provide evidence for analogy as the main principle behind experts’ acquisition of perceptual knowledge. However, the methodology they used—asking players to pair positions using abstract similarity—raises the possibility that the task reflects more the effect of directional instructions than the principles underlying the acquisition of knowledge. Here we replicate and extend Linhares and Brum’s experiment and show that the matching task they used is inadequate for drawing any conclusions about the nature of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6. Ready Player Two: Women Gamers and Designed Identity.Shira Chess - 2017
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  19
    Let us consider the roles of temperament and of fortuitous events.Stella Chess - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1):21-22.
  8.  19
    What do we learn from the Strange Situation?Stella Chess - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):148-149.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  20
    Behavioral Individuality in Early Childhood.A. Thomas, H. Birch, S. Chess, M. Hertzig & S. Korn - 1965 - British Journal of Educational Studies 14 (1):110-110.
  10. Frege, Thomae, and Formalism: Shifting Perspectives.Richard Lawrence - 2023 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 11 (2):1-23.
    Mathematical formalism is the the view that numbers are "signs" and that arithmetic is like a game played with such signs. Frege's colleague Thomae defended formalism using an analogy with chess, and Frege's critique of this analogy has had a major influence on discussions in analytic philosophy about signs, rules, meaning, and mathematics. Here I offer a new interpretation of formalism as defended by Thomae and his predecessors, paying close attention to the mathematical details and historical context. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Marie-laure Ryan.Creative Analogies - 1998 - Semiotica 118 (1/2):147-164.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  10
    Reply to Devolder.On Reasoning Analogy - 2014 - In Arthur L. Caplan & Robert Arp (eds.), Contemporary debates in bioethics. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 101.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Sam Shpall, University of Sydney.Dworkin'S. Literary Analogy - 2019 - In Toh Kevin, Plunkett David & Shapiro Scott (eds.), Dimensions of Normativity: New Essays on Metaethics and Jurisprudence. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Donald L. Martin.Democracy Analogy Falters - forthcoming - Contemporary Issues in Business Ethics.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  46
    Should we agree to disagree? Pragmatism and peer disagreement.Susan Dieleman & Steven W. Visual Analogies and Arguments - unknown
    In this paper, I take up the conciliatory-steadfast debate occurring within social epistemology in regards to the phenomenon of peer disagreement. I will argue, because the conciliatory perspective al-lows us to understand argumentation pragmatically—as a method of problem-solving within a community rather than as a method for obtaining the truth—that in most cases, we should not simply agree to disagree.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  19
    Frege’s Critique of Formalism.Sören Stenlund - 2018 - In Gisela Bengtsson, Simo Säätelä & Alois Pichler (eds.), New Essays on Frege: Between Science and Literature. Cham, Switzerland: Springer. pp. 75-86.
    This paper deals with Frege’s early critique of formalism in the philosophy of mathematics. Frege opposes meaningful arithmetic, according to which arithmetical formulas express a sense and arithmetical rules are grounded in the reference of the signs, to formal arithmetic, exemplified in particular by J. Thomae, whose “formal standpoint”, according to Frege, is that arithmetic should be understood as a manipulation of meaningless figures. However, Frege’s discussion of Thomae’s analogy between arithmetic and chess shows that Frege does not (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  10
    „Denken wir wieder an die Intention, Schach zu spielen.“: Zur Rolle von Schachanalogien in Wittgensteins Philosophie ab 1929.Ingolf Max - 2020 - Wittgenstein-Studien 11 (1):183-206.
    Abstract“Let us think of the intention to play chess”. On the Role of Chess Analogies in Wittgenstein’s Philosophy starting from 1929. Chess analogies represent a neglected topic in the studies on Wittgenstein. However, already a closer look at the Philosophical Investigations shows the great variety of contexts in which there are analogies to very different aspects of chess. An examination of the entire Nachlass illustrates Wittgenstein’s ongoing interest in chess which began in 1929 and lasted (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Against Logical Inferentialism.Nick Zangwill - 2021 - Logique Et Analyse 255 (255):275-287.
    I argue against inferentialism about logic. First, I argue against an analogy between logic and chess, before considering a more basic objection to stipulating inference rules as a way of establishing the meaning of logical constants. The objectionthe Mushroom Omelette Objectionis that stipulative acts are partly constituted by logical notions, and therefore cannot be used to explain logical thought. I then argue that the same problem also attaches to following existing conventional rules, since either those rules have logical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19.  75
    Individuating games.Michael Ridge - 2020 - Synthese 198 (9):8823-8850.
    Games, which philosophers commonly invoke as models for diverse phenomena, are plausibly understood in terms of rules and goals, but this gives rise to two puzzles. The first concerns the identity of a single game over time. Intuitively one and the same game can undergo a change in rules, as when the rules of chess were modified so that a pawn could be moved two squares forward on its first move. Yet if games are individuated in terms of their (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  20. Moral worth and skillful action.David Horst - 2024 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 108 (3):657-675.
    Someone acts in a morally worthy way when they deserve credit for doing the morally right thing. But when and why do agents deserve credit for the success involved in doing the right thing? It is tempting to seek an answer to that question by drawing an analogy with creditworthy success in other domains of human agency, especially in sports, arts, and crafts. Accordingly, some authors have recently argued that, just like creditworthy success in, say, chess, playing the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21. An Essay on Material Necessity.Barry Smith - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy (sup1):301-322.
    Where Humeans rule out the possibility of material or non-logical necessity, and thus of any associated knowledge a priori, the German legal philosopher Adolf Reinach defends the existence of a wide class of material necessities falling within the domain of what can be known a priori, for example in fields such as color and shape, rational psychology, law and economics. Categories such as promise or claim or obligation are, in Reinach’s view, exist as nodes in a system of necessary relations, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  22. The Rejection of Objective Consequentialism.Frances Howard-Snyder - 1997 - Utilitas 9 (2):241-248.
    Objective consequentialism is often criticized because it is impossible to know which of our actions will have the best consequences. Why exactly does this undermine objective consequentialism? I offer a new link between the claim that our knowledge of the future is limited and the rejection of objective consequentialism: that ‘ought’ implies ‘can’ and we cannot produce the best consequences available to us. I support this apparently paradoxical contention by way of an analogy. I cannot beat Karpov at (...) in spite of the fact that I can make each of many series of moves, at least one of which would beat him. I then respond to a series of objections. In the process I develop an account of the ‘can’ of ability. I conclude with some remarks about the bearing this attack has on subjective consequentialism. (shrink)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  23. Situationism, Moral Improvement, and Moral Responsibility.Maria Waggoner, John M. Doris & Manuel Vargas - 2022 - In Manuel Vargas & John Doris (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Moral Psychology. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press.
    In this chapter, we recount some of the most pressing objections to character scepticism, pointing out their limitations and, when appropriate, incorporating their suggestions. From here, we consider what empirically informed moral improvement might look like by turning to the skill analogy. While the skill analogy provides a realistic rubric for becoming a better person, many of the questions concerning the details of how moral improvement might take place remain unanswered. When developing expertise in domains like chess (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  21
    Understanding Our Understanding of Strategic Scenarios: What Role Do Chunks Play?Alexandre Linhares & Paulo Brum - 2007 - Cognitive Science 31 (6):989-1007.
    There is a crucial debate concerning the nature of chess chunks: One current possibility states that chunks are built by encoding particular combinations of pieces-on-squares (POSs), and that chunks are formed mostly by “close” pieces (in a “Euclidean” sense). A complementary hypothesis is that chunks are encoded by abstract, semantic information. This article extends recent experiments and shows that chess players are able to perceive strong similarity between very different positions if the pieces retain the same abstract roles (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  25. The Definition of 'Game'.M. W. Rowe - 1992 - Philosophy 67 (262):467 - 479.
    Besides its intrinsic interest, the definition of ‘game’ is important for three reasons. Firstly, in Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations ‘game’ is the paradigm family resemblance concept. If he is wrong in thinking that ‘game’ cannot be defined, then the persuasive force of his argument against definition generally will be considerably weakened. This, in its turn, will have important consequences for our understanding of concepts and philosophical method. Secondly, Wittgenstein's later writings are full of analogies drawn from games—chess alone is mentioned (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  26. Legal inferentialism and semantic inferentialism.Jaroslav Peregrin - unknown
    One of the recent trends in the philosophy of language and theory of meaning is the inferentialist project launched by Robert Brandom (1994, 2000, 2008), elaborating on the approach of Wilfrid Sellars (1953, 1954, 1956, 1974). According to this project, language is to be seen as essentially a rule-governed activity, providing for meaningful utterances in a way analogous to the way in which the rules of chess provide for making one's pawns, bishops or rooks attack one's opponent, checking his (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Wittgenstein. Playing on the Edges of Language.Francesco Valagussa - 2013 - Aisthesis: Pratiche, Linguaggi E Saperi Dell’Estetico 6 (1):291-305.
    This article aims to show the development of Wittgenstein’s conception of language from a pictorial model to a musical model. At first language is considered as a “means of representation” but in the second phase of Wittgenstein’s work the problem of understanding a proposition and the different shades of meaning supports an analogy with the musical dimension. In this perspective, Wittgenstein approaches the idea of language-game.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  83
    The Analogy of being: invention of the Antichrist or the wisdom of God?Thomas Joseph White (ed.) - 2011 - Cambridge, U.K.: W.B. Eerdmans Pub. Co..
    Proceedings of a conference held in Apr. 2008 in Washington, D.C.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Chess and Antirealism.Samuel Kahn - 2023 - Asian Journal of Philosophy 2 (76):1-20.
    In this article, I make a novel argument for scientific antirealism. My argument is as follows: (1) the best human chess players would lose to the best computer chess programs; (2) if the best human chess players would lose to the best computer chess programs, then there is good reason to think that the best human chess players do not understand how to make winning moves; (3) if there is good reason to think that the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. The Analogy of City and Soul in Plato's Republic.Bernard Williams - 1999 - In Gail Fine (ed.), Plato, Volume 2: Ethics, Politics, Religious and the Soul. Oxford University Press. pp. 255-264.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  31.  79
    Should chess and other mind sports be regarded as sports?Filip Kobiela - 2018 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 45 (3):279-295.
    ABSTRACTIn the philosophy of sport, an opinion that chess is in fact not sports because it lacks physical skills is a standard position. I call the argument that leads to this conclusion a mind sport syllogism. Its analysis enables me to explicate four possible positions concerning the sport-status of chess. Apart from the standard position, which excludes chess from the sport family, I also present analysis of other possible positions, which – for various reasons – do not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  32. Chess composition as an art.Miro Brada - manuscript
    The article presents the chess composition as a logical art, with concrete examples. It began with Arabic mansuba, and later evolved to new-strategy designed by Italian Alberto Mari. The redefinition of mate (e.g. mate with a free field) or a theme to quasi-pseudo theme, opens the new space for combinations, and enables to connect it with other fields like computer science. The article was exhibited in Holland Park, W8 6LU, The Ice House between 18. Oct - 3. Nov. 2013.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Chess and the conscious mind: Why Dreyfus and McDowell got it wrong.Barbara Gail Montero - 2018 - Mind and Language 34 (3):376-392.
    Mind &Language, Volume 34, Issue 3, Page 376-392, June 2019.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34. Chess is Not a Game.Deborah P. Vossen - 2008 - In Benjamin Hale (ed.), Philosophy Looks at Chess. Chicago and La Salle, Illinois: Open Court Press. pp. 191-208.
    As described in Benjamin Hale’s Introduction to “Philosophy Looks at Chess”: -/- “Deb Vossen asks whether chess can rightly be considered a game in the first place. She concludes, much to the surprise of many readers, that chess is not a game. Her evocative claim turns on a distinction between a game and the idea of a game, which evolved out of Bernard Suits’s phenomenally underappreciated work The Grasshopper: Games, Life and Utopia. She advances this position by (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  35.  80
    Chess, Imagination, and Perceptual Understanding.Paul Coates - 2013 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 73:211-242.
    Chess is sometimes referred to as a ‘mind-sport’. Yet, in obvious ways, chess is very unlike physical sports such as tennis and soccer; it doesn't require the levels of fitness and athleticism necessary for such sports. Nor does it involve the sensory-governed, skilled behaviour required in activities such as juggling or snooker. Nevertheless, I suggest, chess is closer than it may at first seem to some of these sporting activities. In particular, there are interesting connections between the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  54
    V*—Chess and Life: The Structure of a Moral Code.Nicholas Denyer - 1982 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 82 (1):59-68.
    Nicholas Denyer; V*—Chess and Life: The Structure of a Moral Code, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 82, Issue 1, 1 June 1982, Pages 59–68, https.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37.  45
    Chess, Love, and Values.Valerie Tiberius - 2023 - Analysis 83 (1):123-134.
    Richard Kraut’s intriguing and provocative book, The Quality of Life, offers a sustained defence of strong experientialism (perhaps also a surprising defence, f.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Mastering Chess and Shogi by Self-Play with a General Reinforcement Learning Algorithm.David Silver, Thomas Hubert, Julian Schrittwieser, Ioannis Antonoglou, Matthew Lai, Arthur Guez, Marc Lanctot, Laurent Sifre, Dharshan Kumaran, Thore Graepel, Timothy Lillicrap, Karen Simonyan & Demis Hassabis - 2017 - .
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  39.  40
    Chess, Artificial Intelligence, and Epistemic Opacity.Paul Grünke - 2019 - Információs Társadalom 19 (4):7--17.
    In 2017 AlphaZero, a neural network-based chess engine shook the chess world by convincingly beating Stockfish, the highest-rated chess engine. In this paper, I describe the technical differences between the two chess engines and based on that, I discuss the impact of the modeling choices on the respective epistemic opacities. I argue that the success of AlphaZero’s approach with neural networks and reinforcement learning is counterbalanced by an increase in the epistemic opacity of the resulting model.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  23
    Chess from my Father.Chris Yan - 2015 - Journal of Medical Humanities 36 (4):395-396.
  41.  23
    Analogical Arguments in Persuasive and Deliberative Contexts.Douglas Walton & Curtis Hyra - 2018 - Informal Logic 38 (2):213-262.
    This paper uses argumentation tools such as argument diagrams and argumentation schemes to analyze four examples of argument from analogy, and argues that to proceed from there to evaluating these arguments, features of the context of dialogue need to be taken into account. The evidence drawn from these examples is taken to support a pragmatic approach to studying argument from analogy, meaning that identifying the logical form of the argument by building an argument diagram of the premises and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  24
    Chess Isn't Tough Enough: Better Games for Mind-Machine Competition.Selmer Bringsjord - unknown
    That Strong AI is still alive may have a lot to do with its avoidance of true tests. When Kasparov sits down to face the meanest chessbot in town, he has the deck stacked against him: his play may involve super-computation, but we know that perfect chess can be played by a nite-state automaton, so Kasparov loses if the engineers are su - ciently clever : : : (Bringsjord, 1997b), p. 9; para-.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  49
    The chess room: further demythologizing of strong AI.Roland Puccetti - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):441-442.
  44.  91
    Chess as a model of language.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1982 - Philosophia 11 (1-2):51-87.
  45.  5
    The Chess Game.Batya Weinbaum - 1990 - Feminist Review 36 (1):95-95.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Expert chess memory without chess knowledge-a training study.K. A. Ericsson & M. S. Harris - 1990 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 28 (6):518-518.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47. Chess news it was better not to know.Peter Buse - 2010 - Radical Philosophy 163:59.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  12
    Turing’s 1948 ‘Paper Chess Machine’ Test as a Prototype of the Turing Test.Paweł Łupkowski - 2019 - Ruch Filozoficzny 75 (2):117.
    The aim of this paper is to present the idea which served as a prototype and probably a test field for the idea of the well-known Turing test. This idea is the ‘paper machine’ (an algorithm) for playing chess and the proposal to test its abil-ities in confrontation with a human chess player. I will describe the details of this proposal and discuss it in the light of the Turing test setting.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  89
    Classifying and Analyzing Analogies.Bruce N. Waller - 2001 - Informal Logic 21 (3).
    Analogies come in several forms that serve distinct functions. Inductive analogy is a common type of analogical argument, but critical thinking texts sometimes treat all analogies as inductive. Such an analysis ignores figurative analogies, which may elucidate but do not argue; and also neglects a priori arguments by analogy, a type of analogical argument prominent in law and ethics. A priori arguments by analogy are distinctive, but--contrary to the claims of Govier and Sunstein-they are best understood as (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  50.  12
    Chess Not without the Queen.Virgil C. Aldrich - 1957 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 31:23 - 43.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 1000