Results for 'C. Cummins'

970 found
Order:
  1. Reflection on Reflective Equilibrium.Robert C. Cummins - 1998 - In Michael DePaul & William Ramsey (eds.), Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and its Role in Philosophical Inquiry. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 113-128.
    As a procedure, reflective equilibrium is simply a familiar kind of standard scientific method with a new name. A theory is constructed to account for a set of observations. Recalcitrant data may be rejected as noise or explained away as the effects of interference of some sort. Recalcitrant data that cannot be plausibly dismissed force emendations in theory. What counts as a plausible dismissal depends, among other things, on the going theory, as well as on background theory and on knowledge (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  2. "How does it work" versus "what are the laws?": Two conceptions of psychological explanation.Robert C. Cummins - 2000 - In Robert A. Wilson & Frank C. Keil (eds.), The Shadows and Shallows of Explanation. Cambridge: MIT Press.
    In the beginning, there was the DN (Deductive Nomological) model of explanation, articulated by Hempel and Oppenheim (1948). According to DN, scientific explanation is subsumption under natural law. Individual events are explained by deducing them from laws together with initial conditions (or boundary conditions), and laws are explained by deriving them from other more fundamental laws, as, for example, the simple pendulum law is derived from Newton's laws of motion.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   109 citations  
  3. Why there is no symbol grounding problem?Robert C. Cummins - 1996 - In Robert Cummins (ed.), Representations, Targets, and Attitudes. MIT Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  4. Cross domain inference and problem embedding.Robert C. Cummins - 1991 - In Robert Cummins & John L. Pollock (eds.), Philosophy and AI: Essays at the Interface. MIT Press.
    I.1. Two reasons for studying inference. Inference is studied for two distinct reasons: for its bearing on justification and for its bearing on learning. By and large, philosophy has focused on the role of inference in justification, leaving its role in learning to psychology and artificial intelligence. This difference of role leads to a difference of conception. An inference based theory of learning does not require a conception of inference according to which a good inference is one that justifies its (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Inexplicit information.Robert C. Cummins - 1986 - In Myles Brand & Robert M. Harnish (eds.), The Representation of Knowledge and Belief. University of Arizona Press.
    A discussion of a number of ways that information can be present in a computer program without being explicitly represented.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  6.  73
    Connectionism, computation, and cognition.Robert C. Cummins & Georg Schwarz - 1991 - In Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson (eds.), Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 60--73.
  7.  54
    On an Argument for Truth-Functionality.Robert C. Cummins & Dale Gottlieb - 1972 - American Philosophical Quarterly 9 (3):265 - 269.
    Quine argued that any context allowing substitution of logical equivalents and coextensive terms is truth functional. We argue that Quine's proof for this claim is flawed.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  8. The role of mental meaning in psychological explanation.Robert C. Cummins - 1991 - In Brian P. McLaughlin (ed.), Dretske and his critics. Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell.
  9. Representation and indication.Robert C. Cummins & Pierre Poirier - 2004 - In Hugh Clapin (ed.), Representation in Mind. Elsevier. pp. 21--40.
    This paper is about two kinds of mental content and how they are related. We are going to call them representation and indication. We will begin with a rough characterization of each. The differences, and why they matter, will, hopefully, become clearer as the paper proceeds.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  10. The role of representation in connectionist explanation of cognitive capacities.Robert C. Cummins - 1991 - In William Ramsey, Stephen P. Stich & D. Rumelhart (eds.), Philosophy and Connectionist Theory. Lawrence Erlbaum. pp. 91--114.
  11. Methodological reflections on belief.Robert C. Cummins - 1991 - In R. Bogdan (ed.), Mind and Common Sense: Philosophical Essays on Common Sense Psychology. Cambridge University Press. pp. 53--70.
  12. Truth and meaning.Robert C. Cummins - 2002 - In Joseph Keim-Campbell, Michael O'Rourke & David Shier (eds.), Meaning and Truth: Investigations in Philosophical Semantics. Seven Bridges Press. pp. 175-197.
    D O N A L D D AV I D S O N’S “ Meaning and Truth,” re vo l u t i o n i zed our conception of how truth and meaning are related (Davidson    ). In that famous art i c l e , Davidson put forw a rd the bold conjecture that meanings are satisfaction conditions, and that a Tarskian theory of truth for a language is a theory of meaning for that language. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13. Biological preparedness and evolutionary explanation.Denise D. Cummins & Robert C. Cummins - 1999 - Cognition 73 (3):B37-B53.
    It is commonly supposed that evolutionary explanations of cognitive phenomena involve the assumption that the capacities to be explained are both innate and modular. This is understandable: independent selection of a trait requires that it be both heritable and largely decoupled from other `nearby' traits. Cognitive capacities realized as innate modules would certainly satisfy these contraints. A viable evolutionary cognitive psychology, however, requires neither extreme nativism nor modularity, though it is consistent with both. In this paper, we seek to show (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  14. The internal manual model of psychological explanation.Robert C. Cummins - 1982 - Cognition and Brain Theory 5:257-68.
  15. Epistemological strata and the rules of right reason.Robert C. Cummins, Pierre Poirier & Martin Roth - 2004 - Synthese 141 (3):287 - 331.
    It has been commonplace in epistemology since its inception to idealize away from computational resource constraints, i.e., from the constraints of time and memory. One thought is that a kind of ideal rationality can be specified that ignores the constraints imposed by limited time and memory, and that actual cognitive performance can be seen as an interaction between the norms of ideal rationality and the practicalities of time and memory limitations. But a cornerstone of naturalistic epistemology is that normative assessment (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  16. Explanation and Subsumption.Robert C. Cummins - 1978 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1978:163 - 175.
    The thesis that subsumption is sufficient for explanation is dying out, but the thesis that it is necessary is alive and well. It is difficult to attack this thesis: non-subsumptive counter-examples are declared incomplete, or mere promissory notes. No theory, it is thought, can be explanatory unless it resorts to subsumption at some point. In this paper I attack this thesis by describing a theory that (1) would explain every event it could describe, (2) does not explain by subsumption, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Innate modules vs innate learning biases.Denise D. Cummins & Robert C. Cummins - 2005 - Cognitive Processing.
    Proponents of the dominant paradigm in evolutionary psychology argue that a viable evolutionary cognitive psychology requires that specific cognitive capacities be heritable and “quasi-independent” from other heritable traits, and that these requirements are best satisfied by innate cognitive modules. We argue here that neither of these are required in order to describe and explain how evolution shaped the mind.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  47
    The mind of the matter: Comments on Paul Churchland.Robert C. Cummins - 1984 - Philosophy of Science Association 1984:791-798.
  19. New York branch of the american psychological association.Robert A. Cummins, G. C. Myers, E. L. Cornell, A. I. Gates & A. T. Poffenberger - 1918 - Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 15 (5):130-134.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  77
    Cognitive evolutionary psychology without representational nativism.Denise D. Cummins, Robert C. Cummins & Pierre Poirier - 2003 - Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 15 (2):143-159.
    A viable evolutionary cognitive psychology requires that specific cognitive capacities be (a) heritable and (b) ‘quasi-independent’ from other heritable traits. They must be heritable because there can be no selection for traits that are not. They must be quasi-independent from other heritable traits, since adaptive variations in a specific cognitive capacity could have no distinctive consequences for fitness if effecting those variations required widespread changes in other unrelated traits and capacities as well. These requirements would be satisfied by innate cognitive (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Haugeland on representation and intentionality.Robert C. Cummins - 2002 - In Hugh Clapin (ed.), Philosophy of Mental Representation. Oxford University Press.
    Haugeland doesn’t have what I would call a theory of mental representation. Indeed, it isn’t clear that he believes there is such a thing. But he does have a theory of intentionality and a correlative theory of objectivity, and it is this material that I will be discussing in what follows. It will facilitate the discussion that follows to have at hand some distinctions and accompanying terminology I introduced in Representations, Targets and Attitudes (Cummins, 1996; RTA hereafter). Couching the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. I. Background.Robert C. Cummins, James Blackmon, David Byrd, Pierre Poirier & Martin Roth - unknown
    The current debate over systematicity concerns the formal conditions a scheme of mental representation must satisfy in order to explain the systematicity of thought.1 The systematicity of thought is assumed to be a pervasive property of minds, and can be characterized (roughly) as follows: anyone who can think T can think systematic variants of T, where the systematic variants of T are found by permuting T’s constituents. So, for example, it is an alleged fact that anyone who can think the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Minds, Brains, and Computers: An Anthology.Robert C. Cummins & Denise Dellarosa Cummins (eds.) - 2000 - Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  38
    Philosophy and AI: Essays at the Interface.Robert C. Cummins (ed.) - 1991 - Cambridge: MIT Press.
    Philosophy and AI presents invited contributions that focus on the different perspectives and techniques that philosophy and AI bring to the theory of ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  30
    Representation and covariation.Robert C. Cummins - 1989 - In Stuart Silvers (ed.), ReRepresentation. Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  26.  68
    Dispositions, States and Causes.Robert C. Cummins - 1974 - Analysis 34 (6):194 - 204.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27.  71
    Truth and logical form.Robert C. Cummins - 1975 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 4 (1):29 - 44.
  28.  41
    Reply to Hugly and Sayward.Robert C. Cummins - 1977 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 6 (1):353-354.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Representation and unexploited content.James Blackmon, David Byrd, Robert C. Cummins, Alexa Lee & Martin Roth - 2006 - In Graham Macdonald & David Papineau (eds.), Teleosemantics. Oxford University Press.
    In this paper, we introduce a novel difficulty for teleosemantics, viz., its inability to account for what we call unexploited content—content a representation has, but which the system that harbors it is currently unable to exploit. In section two, we give a characterization of teleosemantics. Since our critique does not depend on any special details that distinguish the variations in the literature, the characterization is broad, brief and abstract. In section three, we explain what we mean by unexploited content, and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  30.  19
    Friedman, JH, 167 Friedman, N., 165.A. Collins, J. L. Coolidge, T. Coote, B. Corrigan, D. D. Cummins, H. B. Curry, J. Czerlinksi, C. Daood, L. Daston & S. B. Datta - 2002 - In Renée Elio (ed.), Common Sense, Reasoning, & Rationality. Oxford University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  21
    Dreyfus, HL, 3% Dreyfus, SE, 396.J. W. Cornman, G. Cottrell, R. Cummins, A. Cussins, L. Darden, C. Darwin, W. Demopoulos, M. Derthick, H. Gardner & M. S. Gazzaniga - 1993 - In Scott M. Christensen & Dale R. Turner (eds.), Folk psychology and the philosophy of mind. Hillsdale, N.J.: L. Erlbaum.
  32.  7
    J. C. B. Gosling and C. C. W. Taylor, "The Greeks on Pleasure". [REVIEW]W. Joseph Cummins - 1984 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 22 (3):366.
  33.  80
    Dominance hierarchies and the evolution of human reasoning.Denise Dellarosa Cummins - 1996 - Minds and Machines 6 (4):463-480.
    Research from ethology and evolutionary biology indicates the following about the evolution of reasoning capacity. First, solving problems of social competition and cooperation have direct impact on survival rates and reproductive success. Second, the social structure that evolved from this pressure is the dominance hierarchy. Third, primates that live in large groups with complex dominance hierarchies also show greater neocortical development, and concomitantly greater cognitive capacity. These facts suggest that the necessity of reasoning effectively about dominance hierarchies left an indelible (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  34.  60
    Analysis and subsumption in the behaviorism of Hull.Robert Cummins - 1983 - Philosophy of Science 50 (March):96-111.
    The background hypothesis of this essay is that psychological phenomena are typically explained, not by subsuming them under psychological laws, but by functional analysis. Causal subsumption is an appropriate strategy for explaining changes of state, but not for explaining capacities, and it is capacities that are the central explananda of psychology. The contrast between functional analysis and causal subsumption is illustrated, and the background hypothesis supported, by a critical reassessment of the motivational psychology of Clark Hull. I argue that Hull's (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  12
    The Book of Bushido: the complete guide to real samurai chivalry.Antony Cummins - 2022 - London: Watkins Media.
    This is the book on bushido, the much-cited but widely misrepresented samurai code of honour. Drawing on authentic historical texts, it is a detailed and accurate exploration of medieval life in Japan and the samurai, a must-have for anyone with a love of martial arts or Japanese history. This is the go-to volume on bushido ("the way of the warrior"), drawing on a wide range of historical sources to paint a vivid picture of the samurai in action and separating the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  18
    The Kāvyaprakāśa in the Benares-Centered Network of Sanskrit Learning.Patrick T. Cummins - 2020 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 48 (3):353-384.
    This article tells an intellectual history of Mammaṭa Bhaṭṭa’s Kāvyaprakāśa in the Benares-Centered Network of Sanskrit Learning from c. 1600–1750 CE. The core narrative proposed herein is that the discourse on Sanskrit Poetics reaches a bifurcated state by the 1400s and 1500s: the Kāvyaprakāśa commentarial tradition constitutes a distinct domain, wherein commentators debate exclusively among themselves on lower-order issues. This period of normalcy is ruptured by Appayya Dīkṣita, who effectively destabilizes the discourse, overhauling the conventional wisdom via his empiricist polemics (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  62
    Eva C. Keuls, "Plato and Greek Painting". [REVIEW]W. Joseph Cummins - 1982 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 20 (1):91.
  38.  4
    "Plato: Philebus", trans., with notes and comm., J. C. B. Gosling. [REVIEW]W. Joseph Cummins - 1978 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 16 (2):221.
  39. R. Cummins, The Nature of Psychological Explanation Reviewed by.C. Hooker - 1987 - Philosophy in Review 7 (6):223-228.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  43
    The World in the Head, by Robert Cummins.C. Price - 2012 - Mind 121 (481):169-172.
  41. Kinds and their Terms: On the Language and Ontology of the Normative and the Empirical.Joseph C. Long - 2009 - Dissertation,
    At the intersection of meta-ethics and philosophy of science, Nicholas Sturgeon’s “Moral Explanation” ([1985] 1988), Richard Boyd’s “How to be a Moral Realist” (1988), and David Brink’s Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (1989) inaugurated a sustained argument for the claim that moral kinds like right action and virtuous agent are scientifically investigable natural kinds. The corresponding position is called “non-reductive ethical naturalism,” or “NEN.” Ethical nonnaturalists, by contrast, argue that moral kinds are genuine and objective, but not natural. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  94
    Clark Hull, Robert Cummins, and functional analysis.Ron Amundson & Laurence D. Smith - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (December):657-666.
    Robert Cummins has recently used the program of Clark Hull to illustrate the effects of logical positivist epistemology upon psychological theory. On Cummins's account, Hull's theory is best understood as a functional analysis, rather than a nomological subsumption. Hull's commitment to the logical positivist view of explanation is said to have blinded him to this aspect of this theory, and thus restricted its scope. We will argue that this interpretation of Hull's epistemology, though common, is mistaken. Hull's epistemological (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  43.  92
    The Modularity of Mind.Robert Cummins & Jerry Fodor - 1983 - Philosophical Review 94 (1):101.
  44.  54
    Hume on the Abstract Idea of Existence: Comments on Cummins' "Hume on the Idea of Existence".Fred Wilson - 1991 - Hume Studies 17 (2):167-201.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume on the Abstract Idea of Existence: Comments on Cummins' "Hume on the Idea of Existence"1 Fred Wilson Hume'sviews on theconceptofexistence: thisisone ofthemore obscure parts of Hume's philosophy. Professor Cummins has done a valuable service simply by trying to unravel some ofthe puzzles; it is still more valuable for shedding as much light as it does on the issues. There are nonetheless problems with the interpretation that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45. Systematicity and the Cognition of Structured Domains.Robert Cummins, James Blackmon, David Byrd, Pierre Poirier, Martin Roth & Georg Schwarz - 2001 - Journal of Philosophy 98 (4):167 - 185.
    The current debate over systematicity concerns the formal conditions a scheme of mental representation must satisfy in order to explain the systematicity of thought.1 The systematicity of thought is assumed to be a pervasive property of minds, and can be characterized (roughly) as follows: anyone who can think T can think systematic variants of T, where the systematic variants of T are found by permuting T’s constituents. So, for example, it is an alleged fact that anyone who can think the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  46.  30
    Can humans form hierarchically embedded mental representations?Denise Dellarosa Cummins - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (5):687-688.
    Certain recurring themes have emerged from research on intelligent behavior from literatures as diverse as developmental psychology, artificial intelligence, human reasoning and problem solving, and primatology. These themes include the importance of sensitivity to goal structure rather than action sequences in intelligent learning, the capacity to construct and manipulate hierarchically embedded mental representations, and a troubling domain specificity in the manifestation of each.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  93
    Aristotle's De interpretatione: contradiction and dialectic.C. W. A. Whitaker - 1996 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    De Interpretatione is among Aristotle's most influential and widely read writings; C. W. A. Whitaker presents the first systematic study of this work, and offers a radical new view of its aims, its structure, and its place in Aristotle's system. He shows that De Interpretatione is not a disjointed essay on ill-connected subjects, as traditionally thought, but a highly organized and systematic treatise on logic, argument, and dialectic.
  48. Toward a Formal Intermediary Between Semantic Representations and the Transformational Component.Cummins Gm - 1976 - Foundations of Language 14 (4):549-560.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. The modularity of mind. [REVIEW]Robert Cummins - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (1):101-108.
  50.  18
    How the Social Environment Shaped the Evolution of Mind.Denise Dellarosa Cummins - 2000 - Synthese 122 (1-2):3-28.
    Dominance hierarchies are ubiquitous in the societies of human and non-human animals. Evidence from comparative, developmental, and cognitive psychological investigations is presented that show how social dominance hierarchies shaped the evolution of the human mind, and hence, human social institutions. It is argued that the pressures that arise from living in hierarchical social groups laid a foundation of fundamental concepts and cognitive strategies that are crucial to surviving in social dominance hierarchies. These include recognizing and reasoning transitively about dominance relations, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
1 — 50 / 970