Results for ' omniscient interpreter'

995 found
Order:
  1. The omniscient interpreter rides again.Anthony L. Brueckner - 1991 - Analysis (October) 199 (October):199-205.
  2.  25
    The omniscient interpreter rides again.A. Brueckner - 1991 - Analysis 51 (4):199-205.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  3.  64
    Interpreting Davidson’s Omniscient Interpreter.Richard N. Manning - 1995 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (3):335-374.
    Donald Davidson infamously claims that belief is in its nature veridical, and that skepticism is for this reason fundamentally incoherent. To those who take the issue of external world skepticism seriously, Davidson's arguments may seem to involve a conjuring trick. In particular, his invocation of an ‘omniscient interpreter’, whose intelligibility supposedly ensures that our beliefs must be largely true, has the air of incense and lantern-rubbing about it. Davidson's claim has received considerable critical response in the literature, almost (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  89
    Possibly v. actually the case: Davidson’s omniscient interpreter at twenty.Nathaniel Goldberg - 2003 - Acta Analytica 18 (1-2):143-160.
    The publication of Davidson 2001, anthologizing articles from the 1980s and 1990s, encourages reconsidering arguments contained in them. One such argument is Davidson's omniscient-interpreter argument ('€˜OIA'€™) in Davidson 1983. The OIA allegedly establishes that it is necessary that most beliefs are true. Thus the omniscient interpreter, revived in 2001 and now 20 years old, was born to answer the skeptic. In Part I of this paper, I consider charges that the OIA establishes only that it is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  14
    Possibly v. actually the case: Davidson’s omniscient interpreter at twenty.Nathaniel Goldberg - 2003 - Acta Analytica 18 (1-2):143-160.
    Recent anthologizing of Davidson’s articles from the 1980s and 1990s encourages us to reconsider arguments contained in them. One such argument is Davidson’s omniscient-interpreter argument (“OIA”) in “A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge,” first published 20 years ago. The OIA allegedly establishes that it is necessary that most beliefs are true. Thus the omniscient interpreter, now 20 years old, was born to answer the skeptic. In §1 of this paper, I consider charges that the OIA (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  6. Skeptical hypotheses and 'omniscient' interpreters.Steven L. Reynolds - 1993 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (2):184 – 195.
    An attempt to defend Davidson's omniscient interpreter argument against various attempts to show that it does not succeed in showing that most of our beliefs must be true. It doesn't argue that this is a good answer to skepticism.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  50
    Coherence, truth and the `omniscient interpreter'.Vrinda Dalmiya - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (158):86-94.
  8.  12
    Skepticism and Davidson's Omniscient Interpreter Argument.Andrew Ward - 1989 - Critica 21 (61):127-143.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  45
    Ordinary versus super-omniscient interpreters.Peter Marton - 1999 - Philosophical Quarterly 49 (194):72-77.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  92
    The super-omniscient interpreter.Anthony Brueckner - 1999 - Philosophical Quarterly 49 (197):526-528.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  16
    Davidson's omniscient interpreter.Stan Janssens & Jaap Van Brakel - 1990 - Communication and Cognition: An Interdisciplinary Quarterly Journal 23 (1):93-99.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  64
    On the Conceivability of an Omniscient Interpreter.Mark Silcox - 2007 - Dialogue 46 (4):627-636.
    I examine the “omniscient interpreter” (OI) argument against scepticism that Donald Davidson published in 1977 only to retract it twenty-two years later. I argue that the argument's persuasiveness has been underestimated. I defend it against the charges that Davidson assumes the actual existence of an OI and that Davidson's other philosophical commitments are incompatible with the very conceivability of an OI. The argument's surface implausibility derives from Davidson's suggestion that an OI would attribute beliefs using the same methods (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  9
    Causation, Interpretation and Omniscience: A Note on Davidson's Epistemology.Vladimír Svoboda & Tim Crane - 2004 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 11 (2):117-127.
    In 'A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge', Donald Davidson argues that it is not possible for us to be massively mistaken in our beliefs. The argument is based on the possibility of an omniscient interpreter who uses the method of radical interpretation to attribute beliefs, since an omniscient interpreter who uses this method will attribute largely true beliefs to those he is inteipreting. In this paper we investigate some of the assumptions behind this argument, and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  6
    Other Than Omniscient: An Interpretation and Defense of Kant's Rejection of Aristotle's Notion of Finite Reasoning.Nathan Colaner - unknown
    Although actual human omniscience is unimaginable, it is not obvious what it means to be limited with regard to thought. One of Kant's significant contributions to epistemology was his redefinition of the limits of thought. He is explicit about this when he contrasts human, receptive intuition, and the creative intuition that an infinite being would have. Importantly, judging and reasoning are only necessary for a mind that is first affected by an object through sensibility, which is not the case for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  18
    Causation, interpretation and omniscience: A note on Davidson's epistemology.Tim Crane-Vladimìr Svoboda - 2004 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 11 (2):117-127.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  61
    To interpret, or to be omniscient.Wai-Hung Wong - 1993 - Philosophical Papers 22 (3):189-198.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17. Future Contingents and the Logic of Temporal Omniscience.Patrick Todd & Brian Rabern - 2021 - Noûs 55 (1):102-127.
    At least since Aristotle’s famous 'sea-battle' passages in On Interpretation 9, some substantial minority of philosophers has been attracted to the doctrine of the open future--the doctrine that future contingent statements are not true. But, prima facie, such views seem inconsistent with the following intuition: if something has happened, then (looking back) it was the case that it would happen. How can it be that, looking forwards, it isn’t true that there will be a sea battle, while also being true (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  18. Solving the Problem of Logical Omniscience.Sinan Dogramaci - 2018 - Philosophical Issues 28 (1):107-128.
    This paper looks at three ways of addressing probabilism’s implausible requirement of logical omniscience. The first and most common strategy says it’s okay to require an ideally rational person to be logically omniscient. I argue that this view is indefensible on any interpretation of ‘ideally rational’. The second strategy says probabilism should be formulated not in terms of logically possible worlds but in terms of doxastically possible worlds, ways you think the world might be. I argue that, on the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  19.  24
    Selves, Interpreters, Narrators.Deborah Knight - 1994 - Philosophy and Literature 18 (2):274-286.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Deborah Knight SELVES, INTERPRETERS, NARRATORS I Autobiography, understood in die standard sense of someone telling or more frequendy writing the story of her life, has been a periodic focus of philosophical attention. Partly this is because philosophers such as Augustine and Rousseau have written some of the classics of the genre. Recendy, interest in autobiography has been renewed among philosophers concerned widi narrative and especially those concerned widi die (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  9
    Lermontov and the omniscience of narrators.David A. Goldfarb - 1996 - Philosophy and Literature 20 (1):61-74.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Lermontov And The Omniscience Of NarratorsDavid A. GoldfarbGod and fictional narrators are the only beings who are sometimes considered omniscient. God, who is sometimes regarded as not fictional, is frequently also regarded as omnipotent. Narrators, who normally seem to have no sphere of action save for conveying information to readers, particularly when they speak omnisciently in the third person, are not considered to have “power” in any way, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  27
    Generation and Selection of Abductive Explanations for Non-Omniscient Agents.Fernando Soler-Toscano & Fernando R. Velázquez-Quesada - 2014 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 23 (2):141-168.
    Among the non-monotonic reasoning processes, abduction is one of the most important. Usually described as the process of looking for explanations, it has been recognized as one of the most commonly used in our daily activities. Still, the traditional definitions of an abductive problem and an abductive solution mention only theories and formulas, leaving agency out of the picture. Our work proposes a study of abductive reasoning from an epistemic and dynamic perspective. In the first part we explore syntactic definitions (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  37
    Anecdotes, omniscience, and associative learning in examining the theory of mind.Steven M. Green, David L. Wilson & Siân Evans - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (1):122-122.
    We suggest that anecdotes have evidentiary value in interpreting nonhuman primate behavior. We also believe that any outcome from the experiments proposed by Heyes can be interpreted as a product of previous experience with trainers or as associative learning using the experimental cues. No potential outcome is clearcut evidence for or against the theory of mind proposition.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Skepticism and interpretation.Kirk Ludwig - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (2):317-339.
    Donald Davidson has argued that attention to the necessarily public character of language shows that we cannot be massively mistaken about the world around us, and that consequently skeptical doubts about empirical knowledge are misplaced. The arguments Davidson advances rely on taking as the fundamental methodological standpoint for investigating meaning and related concepts the standpoint of the interpreter of another speaker, on the grounds that it is from the interpreter’s standpoint that we discover what constraints are placed on (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  24.  86
    Interpreting Kant's theory of divine commands.Patrick Kain - 2005 - Kantian Review 9:128-149.
    Several interpretive disagreements about Kant's theory of divine commands (esp. in the work of Allen Wood and John E. Hare) can be resolved with further attention to Kant's works. It is argued that Kant's moral theism included (at least until 1797) the claim that practical reason, reflecting upon the absolute authority of the moral law, should lead finite rational beings like us to believe that there exists an omnipotent, omniscient and holy being who commands our obedience to the moral (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  25. Good and Evil: Interpreting a Human Condition by Edward Farley, and: The Evils of Theodicy by Terrence W. Tilley, and: The Co-Existence of God and Evil by Jane Mary Trau.Philip L. Quinn - 1992 - The Thomist 56 (3):525-530.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:BOOK REVIEWS Good and Evil: Interpreting a Human Condition. By EDWARD FARLEY. Minneapolis, Minn.: Fortress Press, 1990. Pp. xxi + 295. The Evils of Theodicy. By TERRENCE W. TILLEY. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 1990. Pp. xii + 277. The Co-Existence of God and Evil. By JANE MARY TRAU. New York, N.Y.: Peter Lang, 1991. Pp. 109. Evil is deeply and endlessly fascinating to the religious mind. On the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  38
    Bounded functional interpretation.Fernando Ferreira & Paulo Oliva - 2005 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 135 (1):73-112.
    We present a new functional interpretation, based on a novel assignment of formulas. In contrast with Gödel’s functional “Dialectica” interpretation, the new interpretation does not care for precise witnesses of existential statements, but only for bounds for them. New principles are supported by our interpretation, including the FAN theorem, weak König’s lemma and the lesser limited principle of omniscience. Conspicuous among these principles are also refutations of some laws of classical logic. Notwithstanding, we end up discussing some applications of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  27.  10
    Davidson and Radical Skepticism.Duncan Pritchard - 2013 - In Ernie Lepore & Kurt Ludwig (eds.), Blackwell Companion to Donald Davidson. Blackwell. pp. 519–532.
    Donald Davidson famously argued, contra radical skepticism, that belief is in its nature veridical. In assessing whether Davidson was successful in this regard, it is first necessary to establish the exact philosophical basis Davidson was adducing for this claim, which is far from clear. In particular, a lot of the critical focus on Davidson's approach to radical skepticism has tended to focus on his appeal to an omniscient interpreter, and yet a closer evaluation of Davidson's antiskepticism reveals that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  19
    The Note of Interpretation: Theistic Finitism as an Aesthetics of Religious Naturalism.Andrew Stone Porter - 2023 - American Journal of Theology and Philosophy 44 (1):70-94.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Note of Interpretation: Theistic Finitism as an Aesthetics of Religious NaturalismAndrew Stone Porter (bio)In our cosmological construction we are, therefore, left with the final opposites, joy and sorrow, good and evil, disjunction and conjunction—that is to say, the many in one—flux and permanence, greatness and triviality, freedom and necessity, God and the World. In this list, the pairs of opposites are in experience with a certain ultimate directness (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  8
    Epistemological Constructivism and the Problem of Global Observer.Diana Gasparyan - 2016 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 47 (1):84-101.
    Discussions related to the detection of objective reality, the truth and lie are still a heated topic in the domain of philosophical epistemology. While certain philosophical contexts and theories suggest that the notion "reality as an independent category" should not be engaged, instead, interpretations, including reciprocal, should be used, others hold it that philosophical discussion cannot continue without reference to the said notion. Different philosophers and scolars approach this problem from different angles. When discussing these topics, philosophers often resort to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  42
    Charity, Supervenience, and Skepticism.Hamid Vahid - 2001 - Metaphilosophy 32 (3):308-325.
    In a number of articles Donald Davidson has argued that the charitable nature of his method of radical interpretation rules out the possibility of massive error and thus refutes Cartesian skepticism. The diversity of such arguments and the suggestions that are all being made under the name of the principle of charity have prompted a large body of conflicting responses, adding only to the obscurity of the issues that are generally associated with the question of skepticism. In this paper I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  45
    Genova, Davidson and Content-Scepticism.Anthony Brueckner - 1992 - Analysis 52 (4):228 - 231.
    This paper is a discussion of A C Genova's defense of Davidson's Omniscient Interpreter anti-skeptical argument ("Analysis", 1991.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  10
    Epistemological Constructivism and the Problem of Global Observer.Д.Э Гаспарян - 2016 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 47 (1):84-101.
    Discussions related to the detection of objective reality, the truth and lie are still a heated topic in the domain of philosophical epistemology. While certain philosophical contexts and theories suggest that the notion "reality as an independent category" should not be engaged, instead, interpretations, including reciprocal, should be used, others hold it that philosophical discussion cannot continue without reference to the said notion. Different philosophers and scolars approach this problem from different angles. When discussing these topics, philosophers often resort to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Sind die meisten unserer Meinungen wahr? Zu Donald Davidsons 'extended claim'.Peter Baumann - 1997 - Logos. Anales Del Seminario de Metafísica [Universidad Complutense de Madrid, España] 4:116-136.
    Are our beliefs mostly true? Donald Davidson has proposed some very interesting arguments in favor of his "extended claim" that most our beliefs must be true. The main aim of this paper is to show that Davidson's arguments are not convincing. The most well known of his arguments is the argument of the "omniscient interpreter". The conceivability of a totally ignorant interpreter, however, shows that this argument fails. Davidson offers two more arguments for his extended claim: one (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Transcending Illusions and Illusions of Transcendence.V. Kenny - 2015 - Constructivist Foundations 10 (2):242-245.
    Open peer commentary on the article “What Can the Global Observer Know?” by Diana Gasparyan. Upshot: Starting from the problem of having to write in a language heavily saturated by realism, this commentary limits itself to restating some key notions of radical constructivism, which, by paying attention to the strict limits of what we can claim to know, can more readily eliminate notions such as the “omniscient interpreter.”.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. What Can the Global Observer Know?D. Gasparyan - 2015 - Constructivist Foundations 10 (2):227-237.
    Context: The detection of objective reality, truth, and lies are still heated topics in epistemology. When discussing these topics, philosophers often resort to certain thought experiments, engaging an important concept that can be broadly identified as “the global observer.” It relates to Putnam’s God’s Eye, Davidson’s Omniscient Interpreter, and the ultimate observer in quantum physics, among others. Problem: The article explores the notion of the global observer as the guarantor of the determinability and configuration of events in the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  20
    Menos es más: davidson y el extravío del escéptico.Jesús A. Coll Mármol - 2007 - Análisis Filosófico 27 (2):145-165.
    Este artículo discute cuál es la mejor forma de entender las consecuencias antiescépticas de la aproximación davidsoniana al pensamiento y el lenguaje. Se rechaza que desde tal aproximación se siga, con o sin la ayuda de un intérprete omnisciente, una refutación de las posiciones escépticas. Se defiende que la filosofía de Davidson ha de ser entendida como un diagnóstico teórico del escepticismo en el que juega un papel fundamental el antirepresentacionismo davidsoniano. Desde esta interpretación no se conseguiría una victoria definitiva (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. The Dialogue Between Religion and Science: Which God?K. Helmut Reich - 2000 - Zygon 35 (1):99-113.
    As exemplified by three cases, difficulties in the dialogue between religion and science not infrequently arise from differing views of God's omnipotence and omniscience. From the side of theology, reflections on the biblical and church‐related sources of those views, on Auschwitz and theproblem of theodicy, on God as Creator of the universe, and on how to read and interpret the Bible show that a view of a God who self‐limits almightiness and all‐knowing in order to grant freedom and functional integrity (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38. La soluzione di Boezio nel dibattito contemporaneo sull’onniscienza divina: un bilancio.Damiano Migliorini - 2016 - Rassegna di Teologia 57:19-53.
    The author analyzes the interpretation of Boethius’ “timelessness solution” developed in contemporary Analytic Philosophy of Religion, and the main objections that have been moved to it, trying to draw some conclusions about its effectiveness (a) in solving the antinomy between omniscience and human freedom; (b) in weakening the argument of Open Theism. La nuova prospettiva teoretica proposta dall’Open Theism impone un approfondimento e una rivalutazione delle soluzioni “classiche” all’antinomia tra onniscienza divina e libertà umana. Tra queste “soluzioni” vi è, com’è (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. The Divine Attributes and Non-personal Conceptions of God.John Bishop & Ken Perszyk - 2017 - Topoi 36 (4):609-621.
    Analytical philosophers of religion widely assume that God is a person, albeit immaterial and of unique status, and the divine attributes are thus understood as attributes of this supreme personal being. Our main aim is to consider how traditional divine attributes may be understood on a non-personal conception of God. We propose that foundational theist claims make an all-of-Reality reference, yet retain God’s status as transcendent Creator. We flesh out this proposal by outlining a specific non-personal, monist and ‘naturalist’ conception (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  40. Logical Omnipotence and Two notions of Implicit Belief.Danilo Fraga Dantas - 2019 - In Tiegue Vieira Rodrigues (ed.), Epistemologia Analítica: Debates Contemporâneos. Porto Alegre: Editora Fi. pp. 29-46.
    The most widespread models of rational reasoners (the model based on modal epistemic logic and the model based on probability theory) exhibit the problem of logical omniscience. The most common strategy for avoiding this problem is to interpret the models as describing the explicit beliefs of an ideal reasoner, but only the implicit beliefs of a real reasoner. I argue that this strategy faces serious normative issues. In this paper, I present the more fundamental problem of logical omnipotence, which highlights (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. No Rationality Through Brute-Force.Danilo Fraga Dantas - 2017 - Filosofia Unisinos 18 (3):195-200.
    All reasoners described in the most widespread models of a rational reasoner exhibit logical omniscience, which is impossible for finite reasoners (real reasoners). The most common strategy for dealing with the problem of logical omniscience is to interpret the models using a notion of beliefs different from explicit beliefs. For example, the models could be interpreted as describing the beliefs that the reasoner would hold if the reasoner were able reason indefinitely (stable beliefs). Then the models would describe maximum rationality, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42. La «soluzione tomistica» nel dibattito analitico contemporaneo sull’onniscienza divina e la libertà umana.Damiano Migliorini - 2016 - Divus Thomas 119:359-395.
    The new theoretical perspective proposed by the Open Theism theologians, compels us to study in depth and to evaluate the “classic” argumentative tools used to solve the ancient antinomy between divine omniscience and human freedom, to which the thesis of the Open Theism try to give an innovative solution. Among these tools – invoked by many authors in the contemporary debate about omniscience, in analytic philosophy of religion – several ones are part of Thomas Aquinas’ thought: the division in primary (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Providence and Mystery: From Open Theism to New Approaches.Damiano Migliorini - 2022 - Segni E Comprensione 36 (103):134-158.
    In the recent debate on Christian theism, the position called Open Theism (OT) tries to solve the dilemma of omniscience and human freedom. In OT, the key word of the human-divine relationship is “risk”: in his relationship with us, God is a risk-taker in that he adapts his plan to human decisions and to the situations that arise from them. “Risk” is the fundamental characteristic of any true love relationship. According to OT, God has no exhaustive knowledge of how humans (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Czy wiedzy Boga nie da się pogodzić z wolnością człowieka? Krytyczna analiza niektórych argumentów.Marek Pepliński - 2012 - Filo-Sofija 12 (19, 4):175-192.
    Is Divine Knowledge Incompatible with Human Freedom? An Analysis of Some Arguments The problem that divine omniscience or divine foreknowledge makes free will impossible belongs to notoriously difficult to solve. In XX century one of the most important interpretation of this difficulty was provided by Nelson Pike. If God believes infallibly and in advance how Smith will act, this fact about the past excludes out all alternatives for Smith. But libertarian account of free will requires alternatives possibilities, so, it could (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45. Lifschitz realizability for intuitionistic Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory.Ray-Ming Chen & Michael Rathjen - 2012 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 51 (7-8):789-818.
    A variant of realizability for Heyting arithmetic which validates Church’s thesis with uniqueness condition, but not the general form of Church’s thesis, was introduced by Lifschitz (Proc Am Math Soc 73:101–106, 1979). A Lifschitz counterpart to Kleene’s realizability for functions (in Baire space) was developed by van Oosten (J Symb Log 55:805–821, 1990). In that paper he also extended Lifschitz’ realizability to second order arithmetic. The objective here is to extend it to full intuitionistic Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, IZF. The machinery (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  46. Modal-Epistemic Arithmetic and the problem of quantifying in.Jan Heylen - 2013 - Synthese 190 (1):89-111.
    The subject of this article is Modal-Epistemic Arithmetic (MEA), a theory introduced by Horsten to interpret Epistemic Arithmetic (EA), which in turn was introduced by Shapiro to interpret Heyting Arithmetic. I will show how to interpret MEA in EA such that one can prove that the interpretation of EA is MEA is faithful. Moreover, I will show that one can get rid of a particular Platonist assumption. Then I will discuss models for MEA in light of the problems of logical (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  47.  1
    The Panpsychist Dimension of Kwame Gyekye’s Theistic Conception of God.Ada Agada - forthcoming - Sophia:1-16.
    Kwame Gyekye’s interpretation of traditional Akan religious thought leads him to the conception of God as a being that possesses the properties of omnipotence, omniscience, and omnibenevolence. Adopting an analytical and hermeneutical method, I argue in this article that Gyekye’s understanding of God as the direct source of the sunsum, or spirit, in the context of his presentation of the sunsum as a wholly immaterial and ubiquitous principle introduces a clear panpsychist dimension to his commitment to theism. I point out (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Foreknowledge Without Determinism.Nathan Rockwood - 2019 - Sophia 58 (2):103-113.
    A number of philosophers and theologians have argued that if God has knowledge of future human actions then human agents cannot be free. This argument rests on the assumption that, since God is essentially omniscient, God cannot be wrong about what human agents will do. It is this assumption that I challenge in this paper. My aim is to develop an interpretation of God’s essential omniscience according to which God can be wrong even though God never is wrong. If (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Non-Normal Worlds and Representation.Francesco Berto - 2011 - In Michal Peliš & Vít Punčochář (eds.), The Logica Yearbook. College Publications.
    World semantics for relevant logics include so-called non-normal or impossible worlds providing model-theoretic counterexamples to such irrelevant entailments as (A ∧ ¬A) → B, A → (B∨¬B), or A → (B → B). Some well-known views interpret non-normal worlds as information states. If so, they can plausibly model our ability of conceiving or representing logical impossibilities. The phenomenon is explored by combining a formal setting with philosophical discussion. I take Priest’s basic relevant logic N4 and extend it, on the syntactic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Wittgenstein, Peirce, and Paradoxes of Mathematical Proof.Sergiy Koshkin - 2020 - Analytic Philosophy 62 (3):252-274.
    Wittgenstein's paradoxical theses that unproved propositions are meaningless, proofs form new concepts and rules, and contradictions are of limited concern, led to a variety of interpretations, most of them centered on rule-following skepticism. We argue, with the help of C. S. Peirce's distinction between corollarial and theorematic proofs, that his intuitions are better explained by resistance to what we call conceptual omniscience, treating meaning as fixed content specified in advance. We interpret the distinction in the context of modern epistemic logic (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 995