Results for 'all-or-none hypothesis'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  12
    A test of the all-or-none hypothesis for verbal learning.Joanna P. Williams - 1962 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 64 (2):158.
  2. The delayed consolidation hypothesis of all-or-none conscious perception during the attentional blink, applying the ST2 framework.H. Bowman, Patrick Craston, Srivas Chennu & Brad Wyble - 2009 - In N. A. Taatgen & H. van Rijn (eds.), Proceedings of the 31st Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  96
    Is conscious perception gradual or dichotomous? A comparison of report methodologies during a visual task.Morten Overgaard, Julian Rote, Kim Mouridsen & Thomas Zoëga Ramsøy - 2006 - Consciousness and Cognition 15 (4):700-708.
    In a recent article, [Sergent, C. & Dehaene, S. . Is consciousness a gradual phenomenon? Evidence for an all-or-none bifurcation during the attentional blink, Psychological Science, 15, 720–729] claim to give experimental support to the thesis that there is a clear transition between conscious and unconscious perception. This idea is opposed to theoretical arguments that we should think of conscious perception as a continuum of clarity, with e.g., fringe conscious states [Mangan, B. . Sensation’s ghost—the non-sensory “fringe” of consciousness, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  4. All-or-none versus a graded process conception of attention.L. R. Fournier & C. W. Eriksen - 1991 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 29 (6):518-518.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  7
    All-or-none assumptions in concept identification: Analysis of latency data.James R. Erickson, Myron M. Zajkowski & Evan D. Ehmann - 1966 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 72 (5):690.
  6.  14
    All-or-none versus incremental learning.Joan E. Jones - 1962 - Psychological Review 69 (2):156-160.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  21
    All-or-none and conservation effects in the learning and retention of paired associates.W. K. Estes, B. L. Hopkins & E. J. Crothers - 1960 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 60 (6):329.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  25
    All or none; A novel choice of primitives for elementary logic.R. H. Thomason & H. Leblanc - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (3):345-351.
  9.  21
    An all-or-none characteristic in the elimination of errors during the learning of a stylus maze.J. A. McGeoch & H. N. Peters - 1933 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 16 (4):504.
  10.  10
    All or None: a Novel Choice of Primitives for Elementary Logic.R. H. Thomason & H. Leblanc - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (1):124-125.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  20
    Tests of an all-or-none model of verbal mediated responding.Kent L. Norman & Irwin P. Levin - 1972 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 96 (2):247.
  12.  11
    All-or-none learning of attributes.Albert S. Bregman & David W. Chambers - 1966 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 71 (6):785.
  13.  17
    Stimulus emphasis and all-or-none learning in concept identification.Thomas R. Trabasso - 1963 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 65 (4):398.
  14.  19
    A fundamental property of all-or-none models, binomial distribution of responses prior to conditioning, with application to concept formation in children.Patrick Suppes & Rose Ginsberg - 1963 - Psychological Review 70 (2):139-161.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  19
    Optimal problem-solving search: All-or-none solutions.Herbert A. Simon & Joseph B. Kadane - 1975 - Artificial Intelligence 6 (3):235-247.
  16.  20
    Consciousness isn’t all-or-none: Evidence for partial awareness during the attentional blink.James C. Elliott, Benjamin Baird & Barry Giesbrecht - 2016 - Consciousness and Cognition 40:79-85.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  10
    Nonstationary performance before all-or-none learning.Peter G. Polson & James G. Greeno - 1969 - Psychological Review 76 (2):227-231.
  18.  8
    Associative and differentiation variables in all-or-none learning.Clessen J. Martin - 1965 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 69 (3):308.
  19.  96
    Is consciousness a gradual phenomenon? Evidence for an all-or-none bifurcation during the attentional blink.Claire Sergent & Stanislas Dehaene - 2004 - Psychological Science 15 (11):720-728.
  20. Consciousness: Individuated Information in Action.Jakub Jonkisz - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6:149261.
    Within theoretical and empirical enquiries, many different meanings associated with consciousness have appeared, leaving the term itself quite vague. This makes formulating an abstract and unifying version of the concept of consciousness – the main aim of this article –into an urgent theoretical imperative. It is argued that consciousness, characterized as dually accessible (cognized from the inside and the outside), hierarchically referential (semantically ordered), bodily determined (embedded in the working structures of an organism or conscious system), and useful in action (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  21.  29
    If priming is graded rather than all-or-none, can reactivating abstract structures be the underlying mechanism?Laurie Beth Feldman & Petar Milin - 2017 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  36
    Consciousness as a graded and an all-or-none phenomenon: A conceptual analysis.Bert Windey & Axel Cleeremans - 2015 - Consciousness and Cognition 35:185-191.
  23.  23
    The Competence of Children: No Longer All or None.Willard Gaylin - 1982 - Hastings Center Report 12 (2):33-38.
  24. Paradox Revisited II: Sets—A Case of All or None.Hilary Putnam - 2000 - In Gila Sher & Richard Tieszen (eds.), Between logic and intuition: essays in honor of Charles Parsons. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 16--26.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  31
    R. H. Thomason and H. Leblanc. All or none: a novel choice of primitives for elementary logic. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 32 , pp. 345–351.Mitsuru Yasuhara - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (1):124-125.
  26. Świadomość jako zindywidualizowana informacja w działaniu : uniwersalna charakterystyka.Jakub Jonkisz - 2016 - Filozofia Nauki 24 (2).
    The aim of the article is to formulate a universal characterization of consciousness, despite the conceptual vagueness of that term. The fundamental aspects of this phenomenon as studied by science consist of four features: its being accessible from the inside and the outside (subjectively and objectively), its being about something (referential), its being bodily determined, and its possessing a certain function (being useful). Approached in this way and in broad terms, consciousness seems to be a graded rather than all-or-none (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  22
    A Hypothesis Concerning the Character of Islamic Art.Asli Gocer - 1999 - Journal of the History of Ideas 60 (4):683-692.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:A Hypothesis Concerning the Character of Islamic ArtAsli GocerWhy Islamic art has the distinctive features it has continues to generate clashing explanations. The Islamic visual treasury has no figural images, for instance, and three-dimensional sculpture or large scale oil painting, but instead contains miniatures, vegetal ornaments, arabesque surface patterns, and complex geometrical designs. To account for the phenomena the following radically opposing theories have been offered: the influence (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  7
    Controlling the urge for a Ca2+ surge: all‐or‐none Ca2+ release in neurons.Yuriy M. Usachev & Stanley A. Thayer - 1999 - Bioessays 21 (9):743-750.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  6
    Simple conditioning as two-stage all-or-none learning.John Theios - 1963 - Psychological Review 70 (5):403-417.
  30.  21
    Forgetting in short-term recall: All-or-none or decremental?Thomas O. Nelson & William H. Batchelder - 1969 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 82 (1p1):96.
  31. Why knowledge is the property of a community and possibly none of its members.Boaz Miller - 2015 - Philosophical Quarterly 65 (260):417-441.
    Mainstream analytic epistemology regards knowledge as the property of individuals, rather ‎than groups. Drawing on insights from the reality of knowledge production and dissemination ‎in the sciences, I argue, from within the analytic framework, that this view is wrong. I defend ‎the thesis of ‘knowledge-level justification communalism’, which states that at least some ‎knowledge, typically knowledge obtained from expert testimony, is the property of a ‎community and possibly none of its individual members, in that only the community or some (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  32.  12
    Review: R. H. Thomason, H. Leblanc, All or None: a Novel Choice of Primitives for Elementary Logic. [REVIEW]Mitsuru Yasuhara - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (1):124-125.
  33.  35
    Too Many Friends or None at All? A “Difference” Between Aristotle and Postmodernity.James McEvoy - 2003 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 77 (1):1-19.
    Diogenes Laertius preserved a saying of Aristotle, “He who has friends can have no true friend.” This was mistranslated by Erasmus and gave rise to the words Montaigne attributed to Aristotle, “O mes amis, il n’y a nul amy.” Kant and Nietzsche both used the saying in this sense, which is in fact a contresens. The original Greek words carried much of the sense of ancient friendship, being a warning against polyphilia and a reminder that intimacy is the central value (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. A plethora of promises — or none at all.Michael Cholbi - 2014 - American Philosophical Quarterly 51 (3):261-272.
    Utilitarians are supposed to have difficulty accounting for our obligation to keep promises. But utilitarians also face difficulties concerning our obligation to make promises. Consider any situation in which the options available to me are acts A, B, C… n, and A is utility maximizing. Call A+ the course of action consisting of A plus my promising to perform A. Since there appear to be a wide range of instances in which A+ has greater net utility then A, utilitarianism obligates (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  7
    “Red-Green” or “Brown-Green” Dichromats? The Accuracy of Dichromat Basic Color Terms Metacognition Supports Denomination Change.Humberto Moreira, Julio Lillo & Leticia Álvaro - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    Two experiments compared “Red-Green” dichromats’ empirical and metacognized capacities to discriminate basic color categories and to use the corresponding basic color terms. A first experiment used a 102-related-colors set for a pointing task to identify all the stimuli that could be named with each BCT by each R-G dichromat type. In a second experiment, a group of R-G dichromats estimated their difficulty discriminating BCCs-BCTs in a verbal task. The strong coincidences between the results derived from the pointing and the verbal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Does consequentialism make too many demands, or none at all?Paul E. Hurley - 2006 - Ethics 116 (4):680-706.
  37.  16
    Soviet genetics and the communist party: was it all bad and wrong, or none at all?Mikhail Konashev - 2020 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 42 (2):1-19.
    The history of genetics and the evolutionary theory in the USSR is multidimensional. Only in the 1920s after the October Revolution, and due in large part to that Revolution, the science of genetics arose in Soviet Russia. Genetics was limited, but not obliterated in the second half of the 1950s, and was restored in the late 1960s, after the resignation of Nikita S. Khrushchev. In the subsequent period, Soviet genetics experienced a resurgence, though one not as successful as geneticists would (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  49
    We all are rembrandt experts – or, how task dissociations in school learning effects support the discontinuity hypothesis.Régine Kolinsky & José Morais - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (3):381-382.
    We argue that cognitive penetration in non-early vision extends beyond the special situations considered by Pylyshyn. Many situations which do not involve difficult stimuli or require expert skills nevertheless load on high-level cognitive processes. School learning effects illustrate this point: they provide a way to observe task dissociations which support the discontinuity hypothesis, but they show that the scope of visual cognition in our visual experience is often underestimated.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  58
    Foundation of statistical mechanics: The auxiliary hypotheses.Orly Shenker - 2017 - Philosophy Compass 12 (12):e12464.
    Statistical mechanics is the name of the ongoing attempt to explain and predict certain phenomena, above all those described by thermodynamics on the basis of the fundamental theories of physics, in particular mechanics, together with certain auxiliary assumptions. In another paper in this journal, Foundations of statistical mechanics: Mechanics by itself, I have shown that some of the thermodynamic regularities, including the probabilistic ones, can be described in terms of mechanics by itself. But in order to prove those regularities, in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  40.  58
    “All animals are conscious”: Shifting the null hypothesis in consciousness science.Kristin Andrews - 2024 - Mind and Language 39 (3):415-433.
    The marker approach is taken as best practice for answering the distribution question: Which animals are conscious? However, the methodology can be used to increase confidence in animals many presume to be unconscious, including C. elegans, leading to a trilemma: accept the worms as conscious; reject the specific markers; or reject the marker methodology for answering the distribution question. I defend the third option and argue that answering the distribution question requires a secure theory of consciousness. Accepting the hypothesis (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. The Second Law of Thermodynamics and the Psychological Arrow of Time.Meir Hemmo & Orly Shenker - 2019 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 73 (1):85-107.
    Can the second law of thermodynamics explain our mental experience of the direction of time? According to an influential approach, the past hypothesis of universal low entropy also explains how the psychological arrow comes about. We argue that although this approach has many attractive features, it cannot explain the psychological arrow after all. In particular, we show that the past hypothesis is neither necessary nor sufficient to explain the psychological arrow on the basis of current physics. We propose (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  56
    None of These Problems Are That 'Hard'... or 'Easy': Making Progress on the Problems of Consciousness.L. Miracchi - 2019 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 26 (9-10):160-172.
    I argue that the traditional distinction between hard and easy problems rests on some inaccurate views about explanation in cognitive science. We should distinguish the question of what gives rise to a phenomenon (the generative question) from what that phenomenon is (the nature question). In many cases throughout the special sciences, an answer to the generative question will not shed significant light on the nature question, nor will it eliminate all conceptually possible alternatives. Meanwhile, the apparent easiness of explaining consciousness (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43. Do English and Mandarin speakers think about time differently?Lera Boroditsky, Orly Fuhrman & Kelly McCormick - 2011 - Cognition 118 (1):123-129.
    Time is a fundamental domain of experience. In this paper we ask whether aspects of language and culture affect how people think about this domain. Specifically, we consider whether English and Mandarin speakers think about time differently. We review all of the available evidence both for and against this hypothesis, and report new data that further support and refine it. The results demonstrate that English and Mandarin speakers do think about time differently. As predicted by patterns in language, Mandarin (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  44. Is the continuum hypothesis true, false, or neither?David J. Chalmers - manuscript
    Thanks to all the people who responded to my enquiry about the status of the Continuum Hypothesis. This is a really fascinating subject, which I could waste far too much time on. The following is a summary of some aspects of the feeling I got for the problems. This will be old hat to set theorists, and no doubt there are a couple of embarrassing misunderstandings, but it might be of some interest to non professionals.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  45
    Fields or firings? Comparing the spike code and the electromagnetic field hypothesis.Tam Hunt & Mostyn W. Jones - 2023 - Frontiers in Psychology 14 (1029715.):1-14.
    Where is consciousness? Neurobiological theories of consciousness look primarily to synaptic firing and “spike codes” as the physical substrate of consciousness, although the specific mechanisms of consciousness remain unknown. Synaptic firing results from electrochemical processes in neuron axons and dendrites. All neurons also produce electromagnetic (EM) fields due to various mechanisms, including the electric potential created by transmembrane ion flows, known as “local field potentials,” but there are also more meso-scale and macro-scale EM fields present in the brain. The functional (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  34
    Twilight of The Genealogy? Or a Genealogy of Twilight? Saving Nietzsche’s Internalization Hypothesis from Naïve Determinism.Brian Lightbody - 2021 - Philosophical Readings 13 (3):183-194.
    The Internalization Hypothesis (I.H.), as expressed in GM II 16 of On the Genealogy of Morals, is the essential albeit under-theorized principle of Nietzsche’s psychology. In the following essay, I investigate the purpose I.H. serves concerning Nietzsche’s theory of drives as well as the Hypothesis’s epistemic warrant. I demonstrate that I.H. needs a Neo-Darwinian underpinning for two reasons: 1) to answer the Time-Crunch Problem of Transformation, and 2) in order to render it coherent with Nietzsche’s physiological determinism as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47. The languages of thought.Lawrence J. Kaye - 1995 - Philosophy of Science 62 (1):92-110.
    I critically explore various forms of the language of thought (LOT) hypothesis. Many considerations, including the complexity of representational content and the systematicity of language understanding, support the view that some, but not all, of our mental representations occur in a language. I examine several arguments concerning sententialism and the propositional attitudes, Fodor's arguments concerning infant and animal thought, and Fodor's argument for radical concept nativism and show that none of these considerations require us to postulate a LOT (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  48.  68
    Comments on Tweyman and Davis.George Nathan - 1987 - Hume Studies 13 (1):98-103.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:98 COMMENTS ON TWEYMAN AND DAVIS Tweyman contends that in Parts X and XI of the Dialogues Philo sets aside his Pyrrhonian or skeptical approach to theology, which consists in falsifying or casting doubt on the hypotheses of Cleanthes, and instead argues for a thesis of his own, viz. what we might call the "indifference thesis" that the original source of all things is morally indifferent. Davis counters with (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  23
    Why Cultural Studies is the End of Thinking.Martin McQuillan - 2013 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 45 (6):693-704.
    This article begins from a consideration of this issue’s contention that ‘central to politicized academic projects … is a critique of the cultural power of institutions’ and in particular pedagogical institutions. It argues that is clear enough what the Editor is thinking of here: he names ‘cultural studies’ as his prime suspect and from here it is not too far a leap to imagine that the pedagogical institution at which his ‘politicized academic projects’ take aim is the university. The article (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  32
    Analogy and confirmation theory.Mary Hesse - 1963 - Dialectica 17 (2-3):284-292.
    The argument from analogy is examined from the standpoint of Carnap's confirmation theory. Carnap's own discussion of analogy in relation to his c*— function is restricted to cases where the analogues are known to be similar, but not known to be different in any respect. It has been argued by the author in a previous work,, and by P. Achinstein, that typical analogy arguments involve known differences between the analogues as well as similarities. Achinstein shows that for such arguments (...) of Carnap's Δ— system of conflrmation functions gives satisfactory values, and it is further shown in the present paper that for these arguments the confirmation never rises above its initial value, irrespective of evidence drown from an analogue. it is argued that even if inductive arguments are to be applicable to the real world, they must in principle be capable of taking into account known differences between the instances of an inductive generalization. Hence Carnap's Δ— system is inadequate as an explication of both induction and analogy.Three conditions are stated as necessary for any confirmation theory which gives a satisfactory explication of analogical inference:I. If two individuals a and b are known to agree in certain properties and differ in others, and if in addition a has a further property, then the confirmation of the hypothesis that b also has this property is greater than its initial confirmation, at least if the weight of the similarities is sufficiently great compared with the weight of the differences.II. The confirmation‐value increases or decreases with the weight of the similarities between the analogues compared with the weight of their differences.III. The confirmation that b has a certain property is greater if a has that property than if a does not have it.The Δ— system sastisfles none of these conditions. Carnap and Stegmüller have now, however, presented a new anxiom system for confirmation functions. the — system, Which is introduced primarily to deal with languages whose primitive predicates fall into families such that each individual can only be qualified by one predicate of each family. They construct a c‐ function which, as well as dealing with a language having two families of such predicates, also depends, unlike the functions in the Δ— system, on similarities between otherwise different individuals. The system is not developed far enough in this Appendix to enable the authors to discuss the confirmation in analogy arguments satisfying conditions I — III above, but it is shown in the present paper that, with a simple generalization of the measure‐function defined by Carnap and Stegmüller, and in the simplest non‐trivial case, condition I — III are all satisfied, indeed a stronger form of condition I is satisfied, in which no known similarity of the analogues is postulated.Finally it is remarked that Carnap and Stegmüller's method of introducing their Δ— system is extremely arbitrary and ad hoc, and an alternative method of introducing is suggested. Bearing in mind the fundamental nature of the argument from analogy in all application of induction to the real world, it is suggesetd that the fundamental inductive inference needing explication is not the inference of‘P1b, from ‘P,1a, but the analogical infeence of‘P2b, from‘P1P2a.P1b,. It is posinitial confirmation of‘P2b, and the confirmation of‘P2b, given‘P2a” and that the later two confirmation‐values are equivalent to those in the Δ— system. It is then shown that Carnap and Stegmüller's new measure‐function follows from their axiom system together with these postulates. Thus some of the arbitrariness of the — system is removed by general considérations regarding inductive and analogical inference. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000