Results for 'Carnap, Rudolph'

(not author) ( search as author name )
992 found
Order:
  1.  43
    The unity of science.Rudolf Carnap & Max Black - 1934 - London,: K. Paul, Trench, Trubner & co.. Edited by Max Black.
    As a leading member of the Vienna Circle, Rudolph Carnap's aim was to bring about a "unified science" by applying a method of logical analysis to the empirical data of all the sciences. This work, first published in English in 1934, endeavors to work out a way in which the observation statements required for verification are not private to the observer. The work shows the strong influence of Wittgenstein, Russell, and Frege.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  2. Rudolph Carnap, Logical Empiricist.J. Hintikka - 1978 - Mind 87 (345):135-138.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3. Rudolph Carnap, Meaning and Necessity. [REVIEW]John A. Oesterle - 1949 - The Thomist 12:106.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  6
    Rudolph Carnap, The Logical Structure of the World, and Pseudoproblems in Philosophy. Translated by Rolf A. George (London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1967, 60s.) Pp. xxvi+364. [REVIEW]William Kneale - 1968 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 18 (4):340-342.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. "Rudolph Carnap, Logical Empiricist." Edited by J. Hintikka. [REVIEW]S. Haack - 1978 - Mind 87:135.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Discussion of Rudolph Carnap: Introduction to Symbolic Logic and its Applications.Jens Erik Fenstad - 1958 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 1:254.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. The Philosophy of Rudolph Carnap.John A. Mourant - 1965 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 14:232-234.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  1
    The Philosophy of Rudolph Carnap. [REVIEW]John A. Mourant - 1965 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 14:232-234.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  22
    The Philosophy of Rudolph Carnap. [REVIEW]John A. Mourant - 1965 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 14:232-234.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  49
    Naess, Arne: Wie färdert man heute die empirische Bewegung? Eine Auseinandersetzung mit dem Empirismus von Otto Neurath und Rudolph Carnap.Eivind Storheim - 1959 - Theoria 25 (3):187-191.
  11.  16
    Rudolf Carnap, logical empiricist: materials and perspectives.Jaakko Hintikka (ed.) - 1975 - Boston: D. Reidel Pub. Co..
    "Homage to Rudolph Carnap."--Hempel, C. G. Rudolf Carnap, logical empiricist.--Wedberg, A. How Carnap built the world in 1928.--Eberle, R. A construction of quality classes improved upon the Aufbau.--Carnap, R. Observation language and theoretical language.--Kaplan, D. Significance and analyticity: a comment of some recent proposals of Carnap.--Wójcicki, R. The factual content of empirical theories.--Williams, P. M. On the conservative extensions of semantical systems: a contribution to the problem of analyticity.--Winnie, J. A. Theoretical analyticity.--Wedberg, A. Decision and belief in science.--Bohnert, H. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  12.  88
    Cornea, Carnap, and Current Closure Befuddlement.Stephen J. Wykstra - 2007 - Faith and Philosophy 24 (1):87-98.
    Graham and Maitzen think my CORNEA principle is in trouble because it entails “intolerable violations of closure under known entailment.” I argue that the trouble arises from current befuddlement about closure itself, and that a distinction drawn by Rudolph Carnap, suitably extended, shows how closure, when properly understood, works in tandem with CORNEA. CORNEA does not obey Closure because it shouldn’t: it applies to “dynamic” epistemic operators, whereas closure principles hold only for “static” ones. What the authors see as (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  13.  14
    Naess, Arne: Wie färdert man heute die empirische Bewegung? Eine Auseinandersetzung mit dem Empirismus von Otto Neurath und Rudolph Carnap. [REVIEW]Eivind Storheim - 1959 - Theoria 25 (3):187-191.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14. Carnap and the Vienna Circle: Empiricism and Logical Syntax.Ramon Cirera (ed.) - 1994 - Rodopi.
    In Rudolph Camap (,) established himself as a professor in Vienna. The philosophical atmosphere awaiting him there was not new to him: the year before he ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  15.  48
    Professor Carnap and probability.William H. Hay - 1952 - Philosophy of Science 19 (2):170-177.
    Most handbooks on statistics and the theory of probability leave the reader in a mysterious tangle of mathematical rules for computing apparently arbitrarily chosen numerical functions. At first sight, then, a treatise on the Logical Foundations of Probability raises hopes that it will be a guide to clarity in these matters. These hopes are strengthened if the reader remembers that the author, Professor Rudolph Carnap of the University of Chicago, is noted for his thesis that philosophy is the study (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  46
    Book Review:International Encyclopedia of Unified Science: Vol. I, Foundations of the Unity of Science: ; No. 1, Encyclopedia and Unified Science; Otto Neurath, Niels Bohr, John Dewey, Bertrand Russell, Rudolph Carnap, Charles W. Morris; No. 2, Foundations of the Theory of Signs; Charles W. Morris; No. 5, Procedures of Empirical Science; Victor F. Lenzen; No. 6, Principles of the Theory of Probability. Ernest Nagel. [REVIEW]Paul Weiss - 1939 - Ethics 49 (4):498-.
  17. In the tracks of the historicist movement: Re-assessing the Carnap-Kuhn connection.Guy S. Axtell - 1993 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 24 (1):119-146.
    Thirty years after the publication of Thomas Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, sharp disagreement persists concerning the implications of Kuhn’s "historicist" challenge to empiricism. I discuss the historicist movement over the past thirty years, and the extent to which the discourse between two branches of the historical school has been influenced by tacit assumptions shared with Rudolf Carnap’s empiricism. I begin with an examination of Carnap’s logicism --his logic of science-- and his 1960 correspondence with Kuhn. I focus on (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  18.  15
    Induction, probabilités et confirmation chez Carnap.Samir Boukhris - 2006 - Revue de Synthèse 127 (1):115-139.
    L'idée d'associer probabilité et induction n'est pas propre au xxe siècle, mais elle a reçu un développement systématique lorsque les philosophes néo-positivistes s'en sont emparés. Dès les années 1940, le philosophe Rudolf Carnap s'est proposé de relever le «défi humien» en fondant une théorie de la confirmation par la construction d'une logique probabiliste dite «inductive». Ce projet avait été esquissé à Cambridge dans les années 1920 par l'économiste John M. Keynes. Examiner le programme de Carnap dans sa totalité, le situer (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  16
    The Popper-Carnap Controversy. [REVIEW]M. K. - 1972 - Review of Metaphysics 26 (1):166-166.
    The first chapters of Michalos’ book give an account of the controversy between Karl Popper and Rudolph Carnap following the former’s critique of Carnap in "Degree of Confirmation". Michalos very compactly summarizes the controversy and argues: 1) that Popper was mistaken when he tried to show that Carnap always identified the quantitative degree of confirmation with the acceptability of scientific theories; 2) that Popper is mistaken in accusing Carnap of confusing classificatory, comparative, and quantitative concepts; 3) that a conflict (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  35
    The 'Umbau' - from Constitution Theory to Constructional Ontology.Johanna Seibt - 1997 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 14 (3):305 - 348.
    The paper traces, historically and systematically, the influence of Carnap’s philosophical program on the writings of Nelson Goodman, focusing on the relationship between Carnap’s Aufbau and Goodman’s Structure of Appearance. In particular, drawing on unpublished material from the Carnap Research Archives, I show that Carnap had already anticipated Goodman’s criticism of the method of quasi-analysis and that Goodman misconstrued the status of this procedure on several counts. I also argue that Carnap’s anti-metaphysical stance left his approach with an explanatory deficit (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  21.  79
    Two paradoxes of semantic information.Thomas Macaulay Ferguson - 2015 - Synthese 192 (11):3719-3730.
    Yehoshua Bar-Hillel and Rudolph Carnap’s classical theory of semantic information entails the counterintuitive feature that inconsistent statements convey maximal information. Theories preserving Bar-Hillel and Carnap’s modal intuitions while imposing a veridicality requirement on which statements convey information—such as the theories of Fred Dretske or Luciano Floridi—avoid this commitment, as inconsistent statements are deemed not information-conveying by fiat. This paper produces a pair of paradoxical statements that such “veridical-modal” theories must evaluate as both conveying and not conveying information, although Bar-Hillel (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  61
    Qualia, Extension and Abstraction.Bowman L. Clarke - 1986 - The Monist 69 (2):216-234.
    Rudolph Carnap’s Aufbau was one of the more ambitious philosophical programs of the twentieth century. His proposal was to begin with elementarerlebnisse —cross sections of one total stream of experience temporally limited by the least perceivable segment of time—and an undefined primitive relation, recollection of similarity, holding between the elementary experiences. Without any further non-logical terms, the goal was to utilize a logic, such as that of Principia Mathematica, and actually to construct logically, or to define formally, all the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Experience and Prediction: An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge.Hans Reichenbach - 1938 - Chicago, IL, USA: University of Chicago Press.
    First published in 1949 expressly to introduce logical positivism to English speakers. Reichenbach, with Rudolph Carnap, founded logical positivism, a form of epistemofogy that privileged scientific over metaphysical truths.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   427 citations  
  24. What is Mathematics, Really?Reuben Hersh - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Platonism is the most pervasive philosophy of mathematics. Indeed, it can be argued that an inarticulate, half-conscious Platonism is nearly universal among mathematicians. The basic idea is that mathematical entities exist outside space and time, outside thought and matter, in an abstract realm. In the more eloquent words of Edward Everett, a distinguished nineteenth-century American scholar, "in pure mathematics we contemplate absolute truths which existed in the divine mind before the morning stars sang together, and which will continue to exist (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  25. In the Mood: Why Vibes Matter in Reading and Writing Philosophy.Helen De Cruz - 2023 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 93:171-191.
    Philosophers often write in a particular mood; their work is playful, strident, strenuous, or nostalgic. On the face of it, these moods contribute little to a philosophical argument and are merely incidental. However, I will argue that the cognitive science of moods and emotions offers us reasons to suspect that mood is relevant for philosophical texts. I use examples from Friedrich Nietzsche and Rudolph Carnap to illustrate the role moods play in their arguments. As readers and writers of philosophical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  9
    At the Roots of Rational Expressivism.Giacomo Turbanti - 2019 - In Luca Bellotti, Luca Gili, Enrico Moriconi & Giacomo Turbanti (eds.), Third Pisa Colloquium in Logic, Language and Epistemology. Essays in Honour of Mauro Mariani and Carlo Marletti. Pisa: Edizioni ETS.
    The early writings of Wilfrid Sellars are characterized by the analysis of themes and problems from Rudolph Carnap's philosophy of language. In particular, Sellars investigated the notion of "material'' rules of inference and explored the possibility of a "pure'' pragmatics. In these initial researches Sellars laid the foundations for his inferentialist analysis of meaning. A crucial component of such an analysis is the seminal form of rational expressivism that Sellars began to develop at the time. In this paper I (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  97
    Philosophy of science: A subject with a great future.Janet A. Kourany - 2008 - Philosophy of Science 75 (5):767-778.
    Among philosophers of science nearly a century ago the dominant attitude was that (in Rudolph Carnap’s words) philosophy of science was “like science itself, neutral with respect to practical aims, whether they are moral aims for the individual, or political aims for a society.” The dominant attitude today is not much different: our aim is still to articulate scientific rationality, and our understanding of that rationality still excludes the moral and political. I contrast this with the growing entanglements within (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28.  87
    Engaging Putnam.Sanjit Chakraborty & James Ferguson Conant (eds.) - 2022 - Berlin, Germany: De Gruyter.
    About this book Hilary Whitehall Putnam was one of the leading philosophers of the second half of the 20th century. As student of Rudolph Carnap's and Hans Reichenbach's, he went on to become not only a major figure in North American analytic philosophy, who made significant contributions to the philosophy of mind, language, mathematics, and physics but also to the disciplines of logic, number theory, and computer science. He passed away on March 13, 2016. The present volume is a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  29
    Two Versions of Meaning Failure: A Contributing Essay to the Explanation of the Split Between Analytical and Phenomenological Continental philosophy.Lucas Ribeiro Vollet - 2023 - Husserl Studies 40 (1):1-23.
    Theories of meaning developed within the analytic tradition, starting with Gottlob Frege, and within continental philosophy, starting with Husserl, can be distinguished by their disagreement about the phenomenon of collapse or failure of meaning. Our text focuses on Frege’s legacy, taken up by Rudolph Carnap, which culminated in a view of the collapse of meaning defined first by a purely syntactic conception of categorial error and second, when Tarski entered the scene, by the paradoxes created by the conflict between (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  78
    A history of philosophy in America, 1720-2000.Bruce Kuklick - 2001 - New York: Clarendon Press.
    Ranging from Joseph Bellamy to Hilary Putnam, and from early New England Divinity Schools to contemporary university philosophy departments, historian Bruce Kuklick recounts the story of the growth of philosophical thinking in the United States. Readers will explore the thought of early American philosphers such as Jonathan Edwards and John Witherspoon and will see how the political ideas of Benjamin Franklin, Thomas Paine and Thomas Jefferson influenced philosophy in colonial America. Kuklick discusses The Transcendental Club (members Henry David Thoreau, Ralph (...)
  31.  60
    Experience and Prediction: An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge.Alan W. Richardson & Hans Reichenbach - 1938 - Chicago, IL, USA: University of Notre Dame Press.
    Hans Reichenbach was a formidable figure in early-twentieth-century philosophy of science. Educated in Germany, he was influential in establishing the so-called Berlin Circle, a companion group to the Vienna Circle founded by his colleague Rudolph Carnap. The movement they founded—usually known as "logical positivism," although it is more precisely known as "scientific philosophy" or "logical empiricism"—was a form of epistemology that privileged scientific over metaphysical truths. Reichenbach, like other young philosophers of the exact sciences of his generation, was deeply (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  32. Verificationist Theory of Meaning.Markus Schrenk - 2008 - In U. Windhorst, M. Binder & N. Hirowaka (eds.), Encyclopaedic Reference of Neuroscience. Springer.
    The verification theory of meaning aims to characterise what it is for a sentence to be meaningful and also what kind of abstract object the meaning of a sentence is. A brief outline is given by Rudolph Carnap, one of the theory's most prominent defenders: If we knew what it would be for a given sentence to be found true then we would know what its meaning is. [...] thus the meaning of a sentence is in a certain sense (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Continental divide: Heidegger, Cassirer, davos (review).Sebastian Luft - 2011 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 49 (4):508-509.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Continental Divide: Heidegger, Cassirer, DavosSebastian LuftPeter E. Gordon. Continental Divide: Heidegger, Cassirer, Davos. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2010. Pp. 448. Cloth, $39.95.Much ink has been spilled on the dispute between Ernst Cassirer and Martin Heidegger that took place in the Swiss resort town Davos in 1929—famous since Thomas Mann staged his Magic Mountain there—and which has since been referred to as the “Davos Dispute.” While the debate (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  33
    Differentiation with Stratification: A Principle of Theoretical Physics in the Tradition of the Memory Art.Claudia Pombo - 2015 - Foundations of Physics 45 (10):1301-1310.
    The art of memory started with Aristotle’s questions on memory. During its long evolution, it had important contributions from alchemists, was transformed by Ramon Llull and apparently ended with Giordano Bruno, who was considered the best known representative of this art. This tradition did not disappear, but lives in the formulations of our modern scientific theories. From its initial form as a method of keeping information via associations, it became a principle of classification and structuring of knowledge. This principle, which (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  24
    Discussion — reviews.Jens Erik Fenstad & Ernest Gellner - 1958 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 1 (1-4):247 – 248.
    Sociology of Faith Werner Stark: The Sociology of Knowledge. The International Library of Sociology and Social Reconstruction, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1958. 36s. net. 356 pp. Carnap Introduces Symbolic Logic Rudolph Carnap: Introduction to Symbolic Logic and its Applications, Dover Publication, New York 1958, $1.85, 241 pp.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Logical Positivism, Naturalistic Epistemology, and the Foundations of Psychology.Richard F. Kitchener - 2004 - Behavior and Philosophy 32 (1):37 - 54.
    According to the standard account, logical positivism was the philosophical foundation of psychological neo-behaviorism. Smith (1986) has questioned this interpretation, suggesting that neo-behaviorism drew its philosophical inspiration from a different tradition, one more in keeping with naturalistic epistemology. Smith does not deny, however, the traditional interpretation of the philosophy of logical positivism, which sets it apart from naturalistic epistemology. In this article I suggest (following recent historical scholarship) that a more careful reading of the leading figure of logical positivism, (...) Carnap, shows an important naturalistic component in his philosophy. Hence, we must reevaluate our standard interpretation of the philosophy of logical positivism and its relation to psychological neo-behaviorism. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  72
    A New Case for Indeterminacy Of Translation.Byeong-Uk Yi - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 39:283-289.
    In this paper, I revisit W. V. Quine’s thesis of indeterminacy of translation. I think Quine’s arguments for the thesis are marred by his controversial assumptions about language that amount to a kind of linguistic behaviorism. I hope to cast a new light on the thesis by presenting a strong argument for the thesis that does not rest on those assumptions. The argument that I present in the paper results from adapting Benson Mates’s objection to Rudolph Carnap’s analysis ofsynonymy (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  46
    A History of Philosophy in America 1720–2000 By Bruce Kuklick, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 2001.T. L. S. Sprigge - 2004 - Philosophy 79 (2):348-350.
    Ranging from Joseph Bellamy to Hilary Putnam, and from early New England Divinity Schools to contemporary university philosophy departments, historian Bruce Kuklick recounts the story of the growth of philosophical thinking in the United States. Readers will explore the thought of early American philosphers such as Jonathan Edwards and John Witherspoon and will see how the political ideas of Benjamin Franklin, Thomas Paine and Thomas Jefferson influenced philosophy in colonial America. Kuklick discusses The Transcendental Club (members Henry David Thoreau, Ralph (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  11
    Theory of Colours. [REVIEW]S. P. - 1971 - Review of Metaphysics 25 (2):352-353.
    The papers comprising Zur Farbenlehre, best known portion of Goethe's writings on color and optics, appeared between 1808 and 1810. Portions of Zur Farbenlehre, translated by the painter Charles Lock Eastlake and frequently reprinted under the title Theory of Colours, achieved immediate notoriety because of Goethe's insistent questioning of Newton's methodology. Acknowledging no mentors except Theophrastus and the physicist Robert Boyle, Goethe compared the Newtonian theory of colors--indelicately, some think--to a once proud castle still revered long after it has fallen (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  10
    Theory of Colours. [REVIEW]S. P. - 1971 - Review of Metaphysics 25 (2):352-352.
    The papers comprising Zur Farbenlehre, best known portion of Goethe's writings on color and optics, appeared between 1808 and 1810. Portions of Zur Farbenlehre, translated by the painter Charles Lock Eastlake and frequently reprinted under the title Theory of Colours, achieved immediate notoriety because of Goethe's insistent questioning of Newton's methodology. Acknowledging no mentors except Theophrastus and the physicist Robert Boyle, Goethe compared the Newtonian theory of colors--indelicately, some think--to a once proud castle still revered long after it has fallen (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  14
    Meaning and necessity.Rudolf Carnap - 1956 - Chicago,: University of Chicago Press.
    "This book is valuable as expounding in full a theory of meaning that has its roots in the work of Frege and has been of the widest influence.... The chief virtue of the book is its systematic character. From Frege to Quine most philosophical logicians have restricted themselves by piecemeal and local assaults on the problems involved. The book is marked by a genial tolerance. Carnap sees himself as proposing conventions rather than asserting truths. However he provides plenty of matter (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  42. Imagination and Interpretation in Kant: The Hermeneutic Import of the Critique of Judgment.Rudolph A. MAKKREEL - 1990
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  43. Parmenides and the void.Rudolph E. Siegel - 1961 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 22 (2):264-266.
  44.  54
    Jan Wolenski Carnap's metaphilosophy.Carnap'S. Metaphilosophy - 2003 - In Thomas Bonk (ed.), Language, Truth and Knowledge: Contributions to the Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 2--27.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. The logical syntax of language.Rudolf Carnap - 1937 - London,: K. Paul, Trench, Trubner & co.. Edited by Amethe Smeaton.
    Available for the first time in 20 years, here is the Rudolf Carnap's famous principle of tolerance by which everyone is free to mix and match the rules of ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   341 citations  
  46.  16
    Hume's Account of General Rules.Rudolph V. Vanterpool - 1974 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 12 (4):481-492.
  47.  18
    Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology.Rudolf Carnap - 1950 - Bobbs-Merrill.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   392 citations  
  48. Rudolf Carnap's analysis of `truth': Reply.Rudolf Carnap - 1948 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 9 (2):300-304.
  49.  23
    Art and Visual Perception: A Psychology of the Creative Eye.Rudolph Arnheim - 1956 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 16 (3):425-426.
  50. Logical foundations of probability.Rudolf Carnap - 1950 - Chicago]: Chicago University of Chicago Press.
    APA PsycNET abstract: This is the first volume of a two-volume work on Probability and Induction. Because the writer holds that probability logic is identical with inductive logic, this work is devoted to philosophical problems concerning the nature of probability and inductive reasoning. The author rejects a statistical frequency basis for probability in favor of a logical relation between two statements or propositions. Probability "is the degree of confirmation of a hypothesis (or conclusion) on the basis of some given evidence (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   875 citations  
1 — 50 / 992