Results for 'William G. Scott'

(not author) ( search as author name )
1000+ found
Order:
  1. Organizational Values in America.William G. Scott & David K. Hart - 1991 - Journal of Business Ethics 10 (6):450-470.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  2. The problem or mystery of evil and virtue in organizations.William G. Scott & Terence R. Mitchell - 1988 - In Konstantin Kolenda (ed.), Organizations and ethical individualism. New York: Praeger. pp. 47--72.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3. Administrative Crisis.William G. Scott & David K. Hart - 2001 - In Willa M. Bruce (ed.), Classics of administrative ethics. Boulder: Westview Press. pp. 410.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Healing relationships and the existential philosophy of Martin Buber.John G. Scott, Rebecca G. Scott, William L. Miller, Kurt C. Stange & Benjamin F. Crabtree - 2009 - Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 4:11-.
    The dominant unspoken philosophical basis of medical care in the United States is a form of Cartesian reductionism that views the body as a machine and medical professionals as technicians whose job is to repair that machine. The purpose of this paper is to advocate for an alternative philosophy of medicine based on the concept of healing relationships between clinicians and patients. This is accomplished first by exploring the ethical and philosophical work of Pellegrino and Thomasma and then by connecting (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  5. John Kekes is Professor of Philosophy at the State University of New York at Albany. Alan S. Waterman is Professor of Psychology at Trenton State College in Trenton, New Jersey. [REVIEW]William G. Scott, Terence R. Mitchell, David K. Hart, David L. Norton, Peter R. Breggin & Konstantin Kolenda - 1988 - In Konstantin Kolenda (ed.), Organizations and ethical individualism. New York: Praeger.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  6.  15
    Expectancy and discrete reaction time in a probability reversal design.E. Scott Geller, Charles P. Whitman, Richard F. Wrenn & William G. Shipley - 1971 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 90 (1):113.
  7.  10
    The Tablets of Ebla: Concordance and Bibliography.Vesna Davidović, Scott G. Beld, William W. Hallo, Piotr Michalowski & Vesna Davidovic - 1987 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 107 (2):330.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  13
    The Business of Consumption: Environmental Ethics and the Global Economy.George G. Brenkert, Donald A. Brown, Rogene A. Buchholz, Herman E. Daly, Richard Dodd, R. Edward Freeman, Eric T. Freyfogle, R. Goodland, Michael E. Gorman, Andrea Larson, John Lemons, Don Mayer, William McDonough, Matthew M. Mehalik, Ernest Partridge, Jessica Pierce, William E. Rees, Joel E. Reichart, Sandra B. Rosenthal, Mark Sagoff, Julian L. Simon, Scott Sonenshein & Wendy Warren - 1998 - Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    At the forefront of international concerns about global legislation and regulation, a host of noted environmentalists and business ethicists examine ethical issues in consumption from the points of view of environmental sustainability, economic development, and free enterprise.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  91
    Persons in Patristic and Medieval Christian Theology.Scott M. Williams - 2019 - In Antonia LoLordo (ed.), Persons: A History. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, Usa.
    Introduction: -/- It is likely that Boethius (480-524ce) inaugurates, in Latin Christian theology, the consideration of personhood as such. In the Treatise Against Eutyches and Nestorius Boethius gives a well-known definition of personhood according to genus and difference(s): a person is an individual substance of a rational nature. Personhood is predicated only of individual rational substances. This chapter situates Boethius in relation to significant Christian theologians before and after him, and the way in which his definition of personhood is a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  66
    Is Faith in God Reasonable? Debates in Philosophy, Science and Rhetoric. [REVIEW]Scott D. G. Ventureyra - 2017 - Science Et Esprit 69 (3):447-451.
  11.  26
    Overturning Stumbling Blocks: A Review of A Reasonable Response Answers to Tough Questions on: God, Christianity and the Bible. [REVIEW]Scott D. G. Ventureyra - 2014 - Convivium 3 (14):38-39.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  5
    Being as Communion: A Metaphysics of Information. [REVIEW]Scott D. G. Ventureyra - 2017 - Science Et Esprit 69 (2):289-292.
  13.  19
    Review: Steven E. Boer, William G. Lycan, Knowing Who. [REVIEW]Scott Soames - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (2):657-659.
  14. Organizational Values in America. By William G. Scott and David K. Hart. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 1989. [REVIEW]David Norton - 1990 - Reason Papers 15:149-153.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  18
    Steven E. Boër and William G. Lycan. Knowing who. Bradford books. The MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., and London, 1986, xiv + 212 pp. [REVIEW]Scott Soames - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (2):657-659.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  12
    Believing & Acting: The Pragmatic Turn in Comparative Religion and Ethics. By G. Scott Davis. Pp. 234, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2012, £30.00. [REVIEW]John R. Williams - 2015 - Heythrop Journal 56 (5):857-858.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  3
    Reflections of the Dream: 1975-1994, Twenty Years Celebrating the Life of Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr. at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Clarence G. Williams - 1996 - MIT Press (MA).
    Bringing together speeches given at the Institute's annual King Day convocation, this book celebrates two decades of commitment by MIT to honoring the memory and furthering the work of Martin Luther King, Jr. In reading these speeches, one catches in reflection twenty years of turmoil and change, some positive (including an increasing number of speakers drawn from the ranks of MIT's African-American alumni/ae) but much negative, in which Dr. King's dream has been a continuing beacon for action. Speakers have included (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  21
    What do you.William D. Harpine - 2004 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 37 (4):335-352.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:What Do You Mean, Rhetoric Is Epistemic?William D. HarpineIn 1967, Robert L. Scott (1967) advocated that "rhetoric is epistemic." This concept has enriched the work of rhetorical theorists and critics. Scott's essay is founded in a concept of argumentative justification in rhetoric, viewed as an alternative to analytic logic. Other writers, including Brummett (1976), Railsback (1983), and Cherwitz and Hikins (1986), have offered variations on (...)'s theme. The thesis that rhetoric is epistemic has been controversial, however, and from the tone of the debate one may draw two conclusions: many rhetorical theorists feel that Scott was on to something important, and the thesis as it has been developed is flawed. Much of the dispute centers on what the thesis means. These discussions have not yet adequately clarified that issue.The philosopher's most fundamental obligation is to define terms with care. It is in precisely this respect that the rhetoric-is-epistemic theorists have fallen short. Some of the key terms in this literature include rhetoric, knowledge, certainty, and truth. In too many cases, the writers on rhetorical epistemology have not defined their key terms at all. In other cases, their definitions are inadequate or inconsistent. This essay undertakes to sort out the most important definitional problems, which center on the rhetoric-is-epistemic theorists' habit of equivocating about the meanings of "rhetoric" and "certainty." The result makes it possible to endorse the validity of Scott's essentially ethical conclusions, while dismissing a number of unnecessary complexities in the arguments made by rhetoric-as-epistemic theorists. Finally, a few alternatives that might lead to more robust foundations for the rhetoric-as-epistemic thesis are suggested.In 1978, after reviewing four distinct interpretations of the claim that rhetoric is epistemic, Leff concluded that clarification of what that claim means "deserves more disciplined treatment than it has received in the recent literature" (1978, 77). The same could still be said. After some [End Page 335] thirty years of active research and speculation on the topic, one now sees fewer publications specifically advocating that rhetoric is epistemic. The distinguished rhetorical theorist Barry Brummett (1990) has declared the thesis deceased (69-72).All the same, textbook authors treat the thesis as a given, despite their tendency to interpret it in wildly different ways. Foss, for example, puts forward a view that "in the field of communication, the idea that rhetoric creates reality is known as the notion that rhetoric is epistemic, which simply means that rhetoric creates knowledge; epistemology is the study of the origin and nature of knowledge" (1989, 122; emphasis in the original). This version of the thesis, claiming that rhetoric actually "creates reality," might be more ontological than it is epistemic.1 Herrick takes a dialectical view that "through rhetorical interaction, people come to accept some ideas as true and to reject others as false. Thus, rhetoric's epistemic function in society can be seen in some ways to be a result of its benefit of testing ideas." Herrick continues that "once an idea has been tested thoroughly by a group, community, and society, it becomes part of what these groups take to be knowledge." Herrick contrasts this with the rejected view that "knowledge is all objective in nature and comes to us by way of direct experience or education" (1997, 22). Both Herrick and Foss offer interesting theses, and both attribute their views to Scott, but their views are obviously very different. There can be no surer evidence of the failure to use terms precisely.Brummett (1990) attributes the demise of rhetoric-is-epistemic research to the failure of critics to employ the idea in rhetorical criticism. Brummett might be right to the extent that much of the rhetoric-is-epistemic literature is indeed exceptionally abstract. Specific discussions might clarify some issues. Nonetheless, some notable rhetorical critics have indeed employed a concept that rhetoric is epistemic (e.g., Scott and Klumpp 1984; Sullivan 1992). The issues remain unclear. Furthermore, rhetorical criticism per se cannot clarify the meanings of theoretical terms. More likely, one sees less and less published research about the thesis that rhetoric is epistemic precisely because the thesis has not been laid out clearly... (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  19.  64
    Associations of prostate cancer risk variants with disease aggressiveness: results of the NCI-SPORE Genetics Working Group analysis of 18,343 cases. [REVIEW]Brian T. Helfand, Kimberly A. Roehl, Phillip R. Cooper, Barry B. McGuire, Liesel M. Fitzgerald, Geraldine Cancel-Tassin, Jean-Nicolas Cornu, Scott Bauer, Erin L. Van Blarigan, Xin Chen, David Duggan, Elaine A. Ostrander, Mary Gwo-Shu, Zuo-Feng Zhang, Shen-Chih Chang, Somee Jeong, Elizabeth T. H. Fontham, Gary Smith, James L. Mohler, Sonja I. Berndt, Shannon K. McDonnell, Rick Kittles, Benjamin A. Rybicki, Matthew Freedman, Philip W. Kantoff, Mark Pomerantz, Joan P. Breyer, Jeffrey R. Smith, Timothy R. Rebbeck, Dan Mercola, William B. Isaacs, Fredrick Wiklund, Olivier Cussenot, Stephen N. Thibodeau, Daniel J. Schaid, Lisa Cannon-Albright, Kathleen A. Cooney, Stephen J. Chanock, Janet L. Stanford, June M. Chan, John Witte, Jianfeng Xu, Jeannette T. Bensen, Jack A. Taylor & William J. Catalona - unknown
    © 2015, Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg.Genetic studies have identified single nucleotide polymorphisms associated with the risk of prostate cancer. It remains unclear whether such genetic variants are associated with disease aggressiveness. The NCI-SPORE Genetics Working Group retrospectively collected clinicopathologic information and genotype data for 36 SNPs which at the time had been validated to be associated with PC risk from 25,674 cases with PC. Cases were grouped according to race, Gleason score and aggressiveness. Statistical analyses were used to compare the frequency (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  29
    What Do You Mean, Rhetoric Is Epistemic?William D. Harpine - 2004 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 37 (4):335 - 352.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:What Do You Mean, Rhetoric Is Epistemic?William D. HarpineIn 1967, Robert L. Scott (1967) advocated that "rhetoric is epistemic." This concept has enriched the work of rhetorical theorists and critics. Scott's essay is founded in a concept of argumentative justification in rhetoric, viewed as an alternative to analytic logic. Other writers, including Brummett (1976), Railsback (1983), and Cherwitz and Hikins (1986), have offered variations on (...)'s theme. The thesis that rhetoric is epistemic has been controversial, however, and from the tone of the debate one may draw two conclusions: many rhetorical theorists feel that Scott was on to something important, and the thesis as it has been developed is flawed. Much of the dispute centers on what the thesis means. These discussions have not yet adequately clarified that issue.The philosopher's most fundamental obligation is to define terms with care. It is in precisely this respect that the rhetoric-is-epistemic theorists have fallen short. Some of the key terms in this literature include rhetoric, knowledge, certainty, and truth. In too many cases, the writers on rhetorical epistemology have not defined their key terms at all. In other cases, their definitions are inadequate or inconsistent. This essay undertakes to sort out the most important definitional problems, which center on the rhetoric-is-epistemic theorists' habit of equivocating about the meanings of "rhetoric" and "certainty." The result makes it possible to endorse the validity of Scott's essentially ethical conclusions, while dismissing a number of unnecessary complexities in the arguments made by rhetoric-as-epistemic theorists. Finally, a few alternatives that might lead to more robust foundations for the rhetoric-as-epistemic thesis are suggested.In 1978, after reviewing four distinct interpretations of the claim that rhetoric is epistemic, Leff concluded that clarification of what that claim means "deserves more disciplined treatment than it has received in the recent literature" (1978, 77). The same could still be said. After some [End Page 335] thirty years of active research and speculation on the topic, one now sees fewer publications specifically advocating that rhetoric is epistemic. The distinguished rhetorical theorist Barry Brummett (1990) has declared the thesis deceased (69-72).All the same, textbook authors treat the thesis as a given, despite their tendency to interpret it in wildly different ways. Foss, for example, puts forward a view that "in the field of communication, the idea that rhetoric creates reality is known as the notion that rhetoric is epistemic, which simply means that rhetoric creates knowledge; epistemology is the study of the origin and nature of knowledge" (1989, 122; emphasis in the original). This version of the thesis, claiming that rhetoric actually "creates reality," might be more ontological than it is epistemic.1 Herrick takes a dialectical view that "through rhetorical interaction, people come to accept some ideas as true and to reject others as false. Thus, rhetoric's epistemic function in society can be seen in some ways to be a result of its benefit of testing ideas." Herrick continues that "once an idea has been tested thoroughly by a group, community, and society, it becomes part of what these groups take to be knowledge." Herrick contrasts this with the rejected view that "knowledge is all objective in nature and comes to us by way of direct experience or education" (1997, 22). Both Herrick and Foss offer interesting theses, and both attribute their views to Scott, but their views are obviously very different. There can be no surer evidence of the failure to use terms precisely.Brummett (1990) attributes the demise of rhetoric-is-epistemic research to the failure of critics to employ the idea in rhetorical criticism. Brummett might be right to the extent that much of the rhetoric-is-epistemic literature is indeed exceptionally abstract. Specific discussions might clarify some issues. Nonetheless, some notable rhetorical critics have indeed employed a concept that rhetoric is epistemic (e.g., Scott and Klumpp 1984; Sullivan 1992). The issues remain unclear. Furthermore, rhetorical criticism per se cannot clarify the meanings of theoretical terms. More likely, one sees less and less published research about the thesis that rhetoric is epistemic precisely because the thesis has not been laid out clearly... (shrink)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  21.  62
    Comments on Michael Polanyi, Scientist and Philosopher.N. E. Wetherick, Brian G. Gowenlock & John Puddefoot - 2007 - Tradition and Discovery 34 (3):31-43.
    This article discusses the 2005 OUP biography of Michael Polanyi by William T. Scott and Martin X. Moleski S.J., Michael Polanyi, Scientist and Philosopher . The discussants are N. E. Wetherick, Brian G Gowenlock, and John Puddefoot; Martin X. Moleski, S. J. briefly responds, providing a previously unpulished letter from Polanyi to Reverend Dr. Knox, a Presbyterian mininster.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Consciousness and Experience.William G. Lycan - 1996 - Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
    Lycan not only uses the numerous arguments against materialism, and functionalist theories of mind in particular, to gain a more detailed positive view of the ..
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   497 citations  
  23. On the Plurality of Worlds.William G. Lycan - 1988 - Journal of Philosophy 85 (1):42-47.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   749 citations  
  24.  25
    On Evidence in Philosophy.William G. Lycan - 2019 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    In this book William G. Lycan offers an epistemology of philosophy itself, a partial method for philosophical inquiry. The epistemology features three ultimate sources of justified philosophical belief. First, common sense, in a carefully restricted sense of the term-the sorts of contingentpropositions Moore defended against idealists and skeptics. Second, the deliverances of well confirmed science. Third and more fundamentally, intuitions about cases in a carefully specified sense of that term. The first half of On Evidence in Philosophy expounds a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  25. Consciousness Explained.William G. Lycan - 1993 - Philosophical Review 102 (3):424.
  26. Consciousness.William G. Lycan - 1987 - MIT Press.
    In this book, William Lycan reviews the diverse philosophical views on consciousness--including those of Kripke, Block, Campbell, Sellars, and Casteneda--and ..
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   229 citations  
  27. Judgement and justification.William G. Lycan - 1988 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Toward theory a homuncular of believing For years and years, philosophers took thoughts and beliefs to be modifications of incorporeal Cartesian egos. ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   307 citations  
  28. Consciousness and Experience.William G. Lycan - 1996 - Philosophy 72 (282):602-604.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   523 citations  
  29. Aristotle on hope.G. Scott Gravlee - 2000 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 38 (4):461-477.
    This paper explores the concept of hope in Aristotle’s philosophy. First, I note that Aristotle contrasts hopefulness with the virtue of courage, although hopefulness can be a source of courage in some contexts, because hopefulness can create confidence. Next, I examine hope in relation to fear, defending Aristotle’s claim that without hope we cannot fear, and suggesting that hope, as a foundation for both fear and confidence, is a fundamental requirement for deliberation. Finally, I look at the hopefulness that underlies (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  30. Mind and cognition: a reader.William G. Lycan (ed.) - 1990 - Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell.
  31.  45
    Real Conditionals.William G. Lycan - 2001 - Oxford, England: Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    This book contends that insufficient attention has been paid to the syntax of conditionals, as investigated by linguists.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   104 citations  
  32.  21
    Believing and Acting: The Pragmatic Turn in Comparative Religion and Ethics.G. Scott Davis - 2012 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    How should religion and ethics be studied if we want to understand what people believe and why they act the way they do? An energetic guide to the study of religion and ethics, rejecting theories from postmodernism and cognitive science in favour of a return to pragmatic enquiry.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33. Consciousness.William G. Lycan - 1988 - Mind 97 (388):640-642.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   245 citations  
  34.  16
    Philosophy of language.William G. Lycan - 2018 - New York: Routledge.
    Now in its Third Edition, Philosophy of Language: A Contemporary Introduction introduces students to the main issues and theories in twentieth-century philosophy of language, focusing specifically on linguistic phenomena. Author William G. Lycan structures the book into four general parts. Part I, Reference and Referring, includes topics such as Russell's theory of descriptions (and its objections), Donnellan's distinction, problems of anaphora, the description theory of proper names, Searle's cluster theory, and the causal-historical theory. Part II, Theories of Meaning, surveys (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  35. Philosophy of Language: A Contemporary Introduction.William G. Lycan - 1999 - New York: Routledge.
    _Philosophy of Language_ introduces the student to the main issues and theories in twentieth-century philosophy of language. Topics are structured in three parts in the book. Part I, Reference and Referring Expressions, includes topics such as Russell's Theory of Desciptions, Donnellan's distinction, problems of anaphora, the description theory of proper names, Searle's cluster theory, and the causal-historical theory. Part II, Theories of Meaning, surveys the competing theories of linguistic meaning and compares their various advantages and liabilities. Part III, Pragmatics and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  36.  33
    Clinicians' “folk” taxonomies and the DSM: Pick your poison.G. Scott Waterman - 2007 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 14 (3):pp. 271-275.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Clinicians’ “Folk” Taxonomies and the DSM: Pick Your PoisonG. Scott Waterman (bio)Keywordsnosology, classification, diagnosis, psychopathologyWith attention turning to the process of formulating the fifth edition of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM-V; e.g., Kendler et al. 2008), the study by Flanagan and Blashfield (2007) of the similarities and differences between clinicians’ “folk” taxonomies and psychiatry’s official one is timely, and its lessons are in need (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Hope in Ancient Greek Philosophy.G. Scott Gravlee - 2020 - In Steven C. Van den Heuvel (ed.), Historical and Multidisciplinary Perspectives on Hope. Cham: Springer. pp. 3-23.
    This chapter aims to illuminate ways in which hope was significant in the philosophy of classical Greece. Although ancient Greek philosophies contain few dedicated and systematic expositions on the nature of hope, they nevertheless include important remarks relating hope to the good life, to reason and deliberation, and to psychological phenomena such as memory, imagination, fear, motivation, and pleasure. After an introductory discussion of Hesiod and Heraclitus, the chapter focuses on Plato and Aristotle. Consideration is given both to Plato’s direct (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38. The continuity of levels of nature.William G. Lycan - 1990 - In Mind and cognition: a reader. Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell. pp. 77--96.
  39.  50
    Mind and Meaning.William G. Lycan - 1984 - Philosophical Review 93 (2):282.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   149 citations  
  40. On the Gettier problem problem.William G. Lycan - 2006 - In Stephen Cade Hetherington (ed.), Epistemology futures. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 148--168.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  41.  23
    Formulation as Diagnosis: Toward a Post-DSM, Post-Biopsychosocial World.G. Scott Waterman - 2014 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 21 (3):211-213.
  42.  27
    The pragmatic turn in the study of religion.G. Scott Davis - 2005 - Journal of Religious Ethics 33 (4):659-668.
    Jeffrey Stout's "Democracy and Tradition" puts forward a complex argument in favor of American democracy as a healthy and legitimate moral and political tradition in itself. Stout does not dwell on the place of his own work in the "pragmatic" approach to the study of religion in the last thirty years. This paper attempts to situate Stout's work in the approach to religion identified with Mary Douglas and Wayne Proudfoot and to suggest some of the consequences for comparative religious ethics (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  43.  54
    modality and meaning.William G. Lycan - 1994 - Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    MEANING POSTULATES REINSTATED If I am right in agreeing with Cresswell that the "logicarrlexicaT distinction is one of degree rather than one of kind, that in turn impugns the distinction between the official truth-rules that define logical ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  44.  7
    Books and Software Reviews-The Uniqueness of the Human Mind?G. Scott Waterman - 2000 - Complexity 5 (5):47-48.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  3
    Science, synthesis, and sanity: an inquiry into the nature of living.G. Scott Williamson - 1980 - Edinburgh: Scottish Academic Press. Edited by Innes Hope Pearse.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. The case for phenomenal externalism.William G. Lycan - 2001 - Philosophical Perspectives 15:17-35.
    Since Twin Earth was discovered by American philosophical-space explorers in the 1970s, the domain of.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  47.  26
    Epistemic Humility: Accruing Wisdom or Forsaking Standards?G. Scott Waterman - 2022 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 29 (2):101-106.
  48.  31
    A Universal Definition of Mental Disorder: Neither Necessary nor Desirable.G. Scott Waterman - 2021 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 28 (4):377-379.
    Psychiatry's relation to the rest of medicine is ambivalent. Its legitimacy as a specialty is often conceived as being closely linked to its fidelity to the fundamental paradigms of medicine, especially the centrality of diagnosis and the association of diagnosis with treatment indications. However, as Gagné-Julien notes, a major impetus behind the quest for a solution to the demarcation problem in psychiatry is "growing concerns regarding over-medicalization". Although it could appear that these two considerations point in opposite directions, both arguably (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  12
    Epistemic Humility, Justice, and Honesty in Clinical Care.G. Scott Waterman - 2022 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 29 (2):127-130.
    When we sit down to write an article that we plan to submit for publication, it is usually because we have completed some piece of empirical or conceptual work that has led us to conclusions we wish to share with our scholarly communities. In this instance, though, my essay under discussion was itself the means by which I sought to draw some conclusions about my recent experiences. Contrary to my initial plans—and my custom—I began writing without a clear idea of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  22
    The undiscovered mind: How the human brain defies replication, medication, and explanation, by John Horgan.G. Scott Waterman - 2000 - Complexity 5 (5):47-48.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000