Results for 'David Efird'

(not author) ( search as author name )
966 found
Order:
  1. What is the principle of recombination?David Efird & Tom Stoneham - 2008 - Dialectica 62 (4):483-494.
    In this paper, we give a precise characterization of the principle of recombination and argue that it need not be subject to any restrictions.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  2. Shattered Faith: The Social Epistemology of Deconversion by Spiritually Violent Religious Trauma.David Efird, Joshua Cockayne & Jack Warman - 2020 - In Michelle Panchuk & Michael C. Rea (eds.), Voices from The Edge: Centering Marginalized Perspectives in Analytic Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    In this chapter, we argue that it’s possible to lose your faith in God by the actions of other people. In particular, we argue that spiritually violent religious trauma, where religious texts are used to shame a person into thinking themselves unworthy of God’s love, can cause a person to stop engaging in activities that sustain their faith in God, such as engaging in the worship of God. To do this, we provide an analysis of faith, worship, and love on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3. Genuine modal realism and the empty world.David Efird & Tom Stoneham - 2005 - European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 1 (1):21-37.
    We argue that genuine modal realism can be extended, rather than modified, so as to allow for the possibility of nothing concrete, a possibility we term ‘metaphysical nihilism’. The issue should be important to the genuine modal realist because, not only is metaphysical nihilism itself intuitively plausible, but also it is supported by an argument with pre-theoretically credible premises, namely, the subtraction argument. Given the soundness of the subtraction argument, we show that there are two ways that the genuine modal (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  4. Critical review of Eleonore Stump's wandering in darkness: Narrative and the problem of suffering.David Efird & David Worsley - 2015 - Philosophical Quarterly 65 (260):547-558.
  5. After Pascal’s Wager: on religious belief, regulated and rationally held.Jack Warman & David Efird - 2021 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 90 (1):61-78.
    In Pascal’s famous wager, he claims that the seeking non-believer can induce genuine religious belief in herself by joining a religious community and taking part in its rituals. This form of belief regulation is epistemologically puzzling: can we form beliefs in this way, and could such beliefs be rationally held? In the first half of the paper, we explain how the regimen could allow the seeking non-believer to regulate her religious beliefs by intervening on her evidence and epistemic standards. In (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  39
    Stages of life: A new metaphysics of conceptionism.David Efird & Stephen Holland - 2019 - Bioethics 33 (4):529-535.
    When a human being comes into existence is crucial in bioethics. Conceptionism is the view that a human being comes into existence at conception. The twinning argument is an influential objection to this view. All versions of the twinning argument rely on a metaphysics of material objects, namely, endurantism. Given this, a strategy for defending conceptionism against the twinning argument is to deny endurantism and adopt an alternative metaphysics of material objects. A version of this strategy which has been debated (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  61
    What an Apophaticist Can Know.David Efird & David Worsley - 2017 - Philosophy and Theology 29 (2):205-219.
    For an apophatic theologian, the doctrines of divine ineffability and of the beatific vision seem, on first glance, to contradict each other. If God is beyond knowledge how can we come to know Him, fully and completely? To resolve this problem, we argue that, if there are at least two qualitatively different kinds of knowledge, namely, propositional knowledge and knowledge of persons, then there are at least two qualitatively different kinds of ineffability, namely, propositional ineffability and what we will call (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8. Is metaphysical nihilism interesting?David Efird & Tom Stoneham - 2009 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90 (2):210-231.
    Suppose nothing exists. Then it is true that nothing exists. What makes that true? Nothing! So it seems that if nothing existed, then the principle that every truth is made true by something (the truthmaker principle) would be false. So if it is possible that nothing exists, a claim often called 'metaphysical nihilism', then the truthmaker principle is not necessary. This paper explores various ways to resolve this conflict without restricting metaphysical nihilism in such a way that it would become (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  9. Combinatorialism and the possibility of nothing.David Efird & Tom Stoneham - 2006 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (2):269 – 280.
    We argue that Armstrong's Combinatorialism allows for the possibility of nothing by giving a Combinatorial account of the empty world and show that such an account is consistent with the ontological and conceptual aims of the theory. We then suggest that the Combinatorialist should allow for this possibility given some methodological considerations. Consequently, rather than being 'spoils for the victor', as Armstrong maintains, deciding whether there might have been nothing helps to determine which metaphysics of modality is to be preferred.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  10. Justifying metaphysical nihilism: A response to Cameron.David Efird & Tom Stoneham - 2009 - Philosophical Quarterly 59 (234):132-137.
    Ross Cameron charges the subtraction argument for metaphysical nihilism with equivocation: each premise is plausible only under different interpretations of 'concrete'. This charge is ungrounded; the argument is both valid and supported by basic modal intuitions.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11. Is Timothy Williamson a Necessary Existent.David Efird - 2010 - In Bob Hale & Aviv Hoffmann (eds.), Modality: Metaphysics, Logic, and Epistemology. Oxford University Press.
    Timothy Williamson (2002) has offered an argument for the claim that, necessarily, he exists, that is, that he is a necessary existent.1 Though this argument has attracted a great deal of attention (e.g., Rumfitt 2003 and Wiggins 2003), I present a new argument for the same conclusion which reveals a new way of denying the soundness of Williamson’s argument, one which denies not only that it is necessary that he exists but also that there are any true necessities about Williamson (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12.  74
    The subtraction argument for the possibility of free mass.David Efird & Tom Stoneham - 2009 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80 (1):50-57.
    Could an object have only mass and no other property? In giving an affirmative answer to this question, Jonathan Schaffer (2003, pp. 136-8) proposes what he calls ‘the subtraction argument’ for ‘the possibility of free mass’. In what follows, we aim to assess the cogency of this argument in comparison with an argument of the same general form which has also been termed a subtraction argument, namely, Thomas Baldwin’s (1996) subtraction argument for metaphysical nihilism, which is the claim that there (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13.  23
    Common Worship.Joshua Cockayne & David Efird - 2018 - Faith and Philosophy 35 (3):299-325.
    People of faith, particularly in the Judeo-Christian tradition, worship corporately at least as often, if not more so, than they do individually. Why do they do this? There are, of course, many reasons, some having to do with personal preference and others having to do with the theology of worship. But, in this paper, we explore one reason, a philosophical reason, which, despite recent work on the philosophy of liturgy, has gone underappreciated. In particular, we argue that corporate worship enables (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  14.  56
    Common Worship.Joshua Cockayne & David Efird - 2018 - Faith and Philosophy 35 (3):299-325.
    People of faith, particularly in the Judeo-Christian tradition, worship corporately at least as often, if not more so, than they do individually. Why do they do this? There are, of course, many reasons, some having to do with personal preference and others having to do with the theology of worship. But, in this paper, we explore one reason, a philosophical reason, which, despite recent work on the philosophy of liturgy, has gone underappreciated. In particular, we argue that corporate worship enables (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  15.  34
    Divine Action and Operative Grace.David Efird & David Worsley - 2017 - Heythrop Journal 58 (5):771-779.
    Operative grace is generally considered to be a paradigm example of special divine action. In this paper, we suggest one reason to think operative grace might be consistent with general divine action alone. On our view, then, a deist can consistently believe in a doctrine of saving faith.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  31
    The Subtraction Argument for the Possibility of Free Mass.David Efird & Tom Stoneham - 2009 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80 (1):50-57.
    Jonathan Schaffer has recently argued that there can be objects having only mass. We show that his argument is either invalid or question begging.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17. Experiencing the Real Presence of Christ in the Eucharist.Joshua Cockayne, David Efird, Gordon Haynes, Daniel Molto, Richard Tamburro, Jack Warman & August Ludwigs - 2017 - Journal of Analytic Theology 5:175-196.
    We present a new understanding of Christ’s real presence in the Eucharist on the model of Stump’s account of God’s omnipresence and Green and Quan’s account of experiencing God in Scripture. On this understanding, Christ is derivatively, rather than fundamentally, located in the consecrated bread and wine, such that Christ is present to the believer through the consecrated bread and wine, thereby making available to the believer a second-person experience of Christ, where the consecrated bread and wine are the way (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18. Truthmakers and possible worlds.David Efird & Tom Stoneham - 2005 - Analysis 65 (4):290–294.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19. Anna Marmodoro and Jonathan Hill , The Metaphysics of the Incarnation, Oxford University Press, 2011.David Efird - 2013 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 5 (2):185-189.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Divine command theory and the semantics of quantified modal logic.David Efird - 2008 - In Yujin Nagasawa & Erik J. Wielenberg (eds.), New waves in philosophy of religion. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 91.
    I offer a series of axiomatic formalizations of Divine Command Theory motivated by certain methodological considerations. Given these considerations, I present what I take to be the best axiomatization of Divine Command Theory, an axiomatization which requires a non-standardsemantics for quantified modal logic.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  54
    God and the ethics of belief: New essays in philosophy of religion - edited by Andrew Dole and Andrew Chignell.David Efird - 2008 - Philosophical Books 49 (1):93-94.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Polarized Yet Warranted Christian Belief.David Efird - 2012 - In Yujin Nagasawa (ed.), Scientific Approaches to the Philosophy of Religion. Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 224.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  3
    Unfenced Existence: The Logic and Metaphysics of Necessary Beings.David Efird - 2002
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. The Resurrection of the Minority Body: Physical Disability in the Life of Heaven.David Efird - 2020 - In Blake Hereth & Kevin Timpe (eds.), The Lost Sheep in Philosophy of Religion New Perspectives on Disability, Gender, Race, and Animals. New York: Routledge.
    This chapter argues that there is no reason that there won’t be physical disabilities in the life of heaven. To argue for this conclusion, the chapter considers what bodies will be good for in the life of heaven. On the one hand, if the life of heaven is physically dynamic, that is, where our bodies change and we can do things with them, like play rugby and climb mountains, physical disabilities can be part of the limitations that allow the physical (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  81
    Non-evidential believing and permissivism about evidence: a reply to Dan-Johan Eklund.Joshua Cockayne, David Efird, Daniel Molto, Richard Tamburro & Jack Warman - 2015 - Religious Studies (1):1-9.
    In response to John Bishop's (2007) account of passionally caused believing, Dan-Johan Eklund (2014) argues that conscious non-evidential believing is (conceptually) impossible, that is, it's (conceptually) impossible consciously to believe that p whilst acknowledging that the relevant evidence doesn't support p's being true, for it conflicts with belief being a truth-oriented attitude, or so he argues. In this article, we present Eklund's case against Bishop's account of passionally caused believing, and we argue that it's unpersuasive, at least to those who (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  48
    Believing by faith: An essay in the epistemology and ethics of religious belief - by John Bishop. [REVIEW]David Efird - 2008 - Philosophical Books 49 (3):283-285.
  27.  15
    Believing By Faith: An Essay in the Epistemology and Ethics of Religious Belief‐ By John Bishop. [REVIEW]David Efird - 2008 - Philosophical Books 49 (3):283-285.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  34
    Review of E. J. Lowe, A. Rami (eds.), Truth and Truth-Making[REVIEW]David Efird - 2009 - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (8).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  3
    Divine Agency and Divine Action, by William J. Abraham. [REVIEW]David Efird - 2021 - Religious Studies 57:179-192.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Lewis's Principle of Recombination: Reply to Efird and Stoneham.George Darby & Duncan Watson - 2010 - Dialectica 64 (3):435-445.
    According to Lewis's modal realism, all ways the world could be are represented by possible worlds, and all possible worlds represent some way the world could be. That there are just the right possible worlds to represent all and only the ways the world could be is to be guaranteed by the principle of recombination. Lewis sketches the principle (put roughly: anything can co-exist with anything else), but does not spell out a precise version that generates just the right possibilities. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  31.  38
    Lewis's Principle of Recombination: Reply to Efird and Stoneham.Duncan Watson George Darby - 2010 - Dialectica 64 (3):435-445.
    According to Lewis's modal realism, all ways the world could be are represented by possible worlds, and all possible worlds represent some way the world could be. That there are just the right possible worlds to represent all and only the ways the world could be is to be guaranteed by the principle of recombination. Lewis sketches the principle , but does not spell out a precise version that generates just the right possibilities. David Efird and Tom Stoneham (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Do Dead Bodies Pose a Problem for Biological Approaches to Personal Identity?David Hershenov - 2005 - Mind 114 (453):31 - 59.
    Part of the appeal of the biological approach to personal identity is that it does not have to countenance spatially coincident entities. But if the termination thesis is correct and the organism ceases to exist at death, then it appears that the corpse is a dead body that earlier was a living body and distinct from but spatially coincident with the organism. If the organism is identified with the body, then the unwelcome spatial coincidence could perhaps be avoided. It is (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  33. Computing Exact Power for Multivariate Repeated Measurements Design.Jimmy Thomas Efird & Kavitha Alimineti - 2005 - In Alan F. Blackwell & David MacKay (eds.), Power. Cambridge University Press. pp. 1.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Reason, Metaphysics, and Mind: New Essays on the Philosophy of Alvin Plantinga.D. Efird - 2013 - Analysis 73 (2):398-400.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  87
    Make/Believing the World(s): Toward a Christian Ontological Pluralism * By Mark S. McLeod-Harrison.D. Efird - 2011 - Analysis 71 (2):404-406.
    ‘We believe in one God, the Father, the Almighty, maker of heaven and earth’, so Christians confess when they recite the Nicene Creed. Now if the argument of Mark S. McLeod-Harrison’s Make/Believing the World: Toward a Christian Ontological Pluralism is correct, God is not alone in that task. We human beings are makers of heaven and earth, too, in the sense that what exists is as it is because our minds have made it so, which is a kind of noetic (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  38
    Philosophical and Theological Essays on the Trinity, edited by Thomas McCall and Michael C. Rea.D. Efird - 2012 - Mind 121 (481):191-195.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  51
    Some Later Medieval Theories of the Eucharist: Thomas Aquinas, Giles of Rome, Duns Scotus, and William Ockham, by Marilyn McCord Adams.D. Efird - 2012 - Mind 121 (482):467-470.
  38.  21
    Sergei Parajanov's Differential Cinema.Robert Efird - 2018 - Film-Philosophy 22 (3):465-483.
    The films of Sergei Parajanov remain some of the most stylistically unique in the history of the medium and easily place him within the pantheon of the world's great filmmakers. This article offers a new perspective on Parajanov's art through a detailed examination of the two works at the center of his oeuvre, The Colour of Pomegranates and The Legend of Suram Fortress. In addition to their undeniable aesthetic value, these films may be appreciated as meaningful discourse on our conceptions (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  87
    Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action.David M. Rasmussen - 1993 - Philosophical Quarterly 43 (173):571.
    This long-awaited book sets out the implications of Habermas's theory of communicative action for moral theory. "Discourse ethics" attempts to reconstruct a moral point of view from which normative claims can be impartially judged. The theory of justice it develops replaces Kant's categorical imperative with a procedure of justification based on reasoned agreement among participants in practical discourse.Habermas connects communicative ethics to the theory of social action via an examination of research in the social psychology of moral and interpersonal development. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   564 citations  
  40.  54
    After Physics.David Z. Albert - 2015 - Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
    Here the philosopher and physicist David Z Albert argues, among other things, that the difference between past and future can be understood as a mechanical phenomenon of nature and that quantum mechanics makes it impossible to present the entirety of what can be said about the world as a narrative of “befores” and “afters.”.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  41. Realist-Expressivism: A Neglected Option for Moral Realism.David Copp - 2001 - Social Philosophy and Policy 18 (2):1-43.
    Moral realism and antirealist-expressivism are of course incompatible positions. They disagree fundamentally about the nature of moral states of mind, the existence of moral states of affairs and properties, and the nature and role of moral discourse. The central realist view is that a person who has or expresses a moral thought is thereby in, or thereby expresses, a cognitive state of mind; she has or expresses a belief that represents a moral state of affairs in a way that might (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  42. David Hume, contractarian.David Gauthier - 1979 - Philosophical Review 88 (1):3-38.
  43. Inverse functionalism and the individuation of powers.David Yates - 2018 - Synthese 195 (10):4525-4550.
    In the pure powers ontology (PPO), basic physical properties have wholly dispositional essences. PPO has clear advantages over categoricalist ontologies, which suffer from familiar epistemological and metaphysical problems. However, opponents argue that because it contains no qualitative properties, PPO lacks the resources to individuate powers, and generates a regress. The challenge for those who take such arguments seriously is to introduce qualitative properties without reintroducing the problems that PPO was meant to solve. In this paper, I distinguish the core claim (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  44.  99
    Human cooperation.David G. Rand & Martin A. Nowak - 2013 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 17 (8):413.
  45.  20
    Visual reaction time and the Broca-Sulzer phenomenon.David Raab, Elizabeth Fehrer & Maurice Hershenson - 1961 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 61 (3):193.
  46. Thinking about Spacetime.David Yates - 2021 - In Christian Wüthrich, Baptiste Le Bihan & Nick Huggett (eds.), Philosophy Beyond Spacetime. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Several different quantum gravity research programmes suggest, for various reasons, that spacetime is not part of the fundamental ontology of physics. This gives rise to the problem of empirical coherence: if fundamental physical entities do not occupy spacetime or instantiate spatiotemporal properties, how can fundamental theories concerning those entities be justified by observation of spatiotemporally located things like meters, pointers and dials? I frame the problem of empirical coherence in terms of entailment: how could a non-spatiotemporal fundamental theory entail spatiotemporal (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  47.  95
    Sound sentiments: integrity in the emotions.David Pugmire - 2005 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    What does it mean for emotion to be well-constituted? What distinguishes good feeling from (just) feeling good? Is there such a distinction at all? The answer to these questions becomes clearer if we realize that for an emotion to be all it seems, it must be responsible as well as responsive to what it is about. It may be that good feeling depends on feeling truly if we are to be really moved, moved in the way that avoids the need (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  48. Hylomorphism, or Something Near Enough.David Yates - forthcoming - In Amanda Bryant & David Yates (eds.), Rethinking Emergence. Oxford University Press.
    Hylomorphists hold that substances are, in some sense, composites of matter and form. The form of a substance is typically taken to play a fundamental role in determining the unity or identity of the whole. Staunch hylomorphists think that this role is of a kind that precludes the ontological reduction of form to the physical and thus take their position to be inconsistent with physicalism. Forms, according to staunch hylomorphism, play a fundamental role in grounding their bearers’ proper parts and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  47
    Problems of multi-species organisms: endosymbionts to holobionts.David C. Queller & Joan E. Strassmann - 2016 - Biology and Philosophy 31 (6):855-873.
    The organism is one of the fundamental concepts of biology and has been at the center of many discussions about biological individuality, yet what exactly it is can be confusing. The definition that we find generally useful is that an organism is a unit in which all the subunits have evolved to be highly cooperative, with very little conflict. We focus on how often organisms evolve from two or more formerly independent organisms. Two canonical transitions of this type—replicators clustered in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  50. The psychology of philosophy: Associating philosophical views with psychological traits in professional philosophers.David B. Yaden & Derek E. Anderson - 2021 - Philosophical Psychology 34 (5):721-755.
    Do psychological traits predict philosophical views? We administered the PhilPapers Survey, created by David Bourget and David Chalmers, which consists of 30 views on central philosophical topics (e.g., epistemology, ethics, metaphysics, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of language) to a sample of professional philosophers (N = 314). We extended the PhilPapers survey to measure a number of psychological traits, such as personality, numeracy, well-being, lifestyle, and life experiences. We also included non-technical ‘translations’ of these views for eventual use (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
1 — 50 / 966