Results for 'Sean Coyle'

(not author) ( search as author name )
1000+ found
Order:
  1. Sean Coyle.Sean Coyle - 1999 - Legal Theory 5 (4):389-413.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Vulnerability and the liberal order.Sean Coyle - 2013 - In Martha Fineman & Anna Grear (eds.), Vulnerability: reflections on a new ethical foundation for law and politics. Burlington, VT: Ashgate.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  18
    The Reality of the Enlightenment.Sean Coyle - 2009 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 17 (4):849-858.
  4.  7
    Modern jurisprudence: a philosophical guide.Sean Coyle - 2014 - New York: Hart.
    This textbook presents a clear exploration of the historical developments and ideas that give modern thinking its distinctive shape. It guides students through the rival standpoints on jurisprudence from the origins of Western jurisprudential thought and the classical tradition to the emergence of 'modern' political thought. Chapters on Hart, Fuller, Rawls, Dworkin and Finnis lead the reader systematically through the terrain of modern legal philosophy, tracing the issues back to fundamental questions of philosophy, and indicating lines of criticism that result (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  5
    Dimensions of Politics and English Jurisprudence.Sean Coyle - 2013 - Cambridge University Press.
    Understandings of law and politics are intrinsically bound up with broader visions of the human condition. Sean Coyle argues for a renewed engagement with the juridical and political philosophies of the Western intellectual tradition, and takes up questions pondered by Aristotle, Plato, Augustine, Aquinas and Hobbes in seeking a deeper understanding of law, politics, freedom, justice and order. Criticising modern theories for their failure to engage with fundamental questions, he explores the profound connections between justice and order and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  7
    Positivism, Idealism and the Rule of Law.Sean Coyle - 2006 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26 (2):257-288.
    The modern lawyer operates within a conception of law as a body of rules. To confront the law of contract, of torts, or of property, is to familiarize oneself with an intricate set of rules. Such familiarity is not yet legal scholarship, much less legal practice. For in order to use the rules as lawyers use them, the rules must be contemplated and considered, and the relationship between the different rules must be understood. Because the intellectual processes involved in handling (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  22
    Practices and the rule of recognition.Sean Coyle - 2005 - Law and Philosophy 25 (4):417-452.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8. Are There Necessary Truths About Rights?Sean Coyle - 2002 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 15 (1):21-49.
    The essay considers whether there are necessary truths about rights. The existence of rights is contingent, but our practices involving rights rest upon fundamental conceptual assumptions necessary to their coherence. Hohfeld's analysis is proffered as the embodiment of those assumptions. An examination of the concept of necessity shows how those assumptions can be necessary truths about rights without being logically necessary.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  8
    Apropos of A Treatise of Legal Philosophy and General Jurisprudence: Volume 1.Sean Coyle - 2009 - Ratio Juris 22 (1):155-170.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  21
    Can Natural Laws be Derived from Sociability?Sean Coyle - 2020 - New Blackfriars 101 (1091):46-66.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  5
    Hart, Raz and the Concept of a Legal System.Sean Coyle - 2002 - Law and Philosophy 21 (3):275-304.
    An underpinning assumption of modern legal positivism isthat the question of how legal standards differ fromnormative standards in other spheres of human thoughtis resolved via the concept of a legal system and thenotion of internal logic, through use of contextualdefinition. This approach is seen to lead to anuntenable form of structuralism altogether atodds with the positivist's intentions. An alternativestrategy is offered which allows the positivists toretain their deepest insights, though at a price.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  9
    Natural Law in Aquinas and Suarez.Sean Coyle - 2017 - Jurisprudence 8 (2):319-341.
    This article considers the relationship between the philosophies of Thomas Aquinas and Francisco Suarez. It has been said that Suarez made significant departures from the natural law theory of Aquinas, by putting greater emphasis on divine command as the source of natural law precepts, and by replacing Aquinas’s focus on good and bad with a focus on right and wrong. Hence, Suarez appears to replace Aquinas’s eudaimonist account of ethics with one based in deontology. The article argues that the differences (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. The Intellectual Commitments of Modern Juridical Thought.Sean Coyle - 2010 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 23 (2):461-482.
    To modern writers, the distinctive achievement of twentieth-century jurisprudence can be viewed as its emancipation from the narrow confines of English utilitarianism, and the subsequent development of perspectives rooted in the fundamental values of justice and rights. The central jurisprudential task of the new century is thus the exploration of a deeper, more elusive moral standpoint, the most profound intellectual commitments of which are yet to be fully digested and understood. My aim in this essay is to reveal something of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  35
    Our knowledge of the legal order.Sean Coyle - 1999 - Legal Theory 5 (4):389-413.
  15.  11
    The Cambridge handbook of natural law and human rights The Cambridge handbook of natural law and human rights, edited by T Angier, I. T. Benson and M. Retter, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2023, xiv + 499 pp., £155 (Hardback) index, ISBN: 9781108939225. [REVIEW]Sean Coyle - 2023 - Jurisprudence 14 (4):571-577.
    This important and intellectually rich collection is a welcome addition to the literature, both on natural law and human rights. Its opening pages, in a reversal of its title, begin with a series o...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  57
    Hart, Raz and the concept of a legal system.Sean Coyle - 2002 - Law and Philosophy 21 (3):275-304.
    An underpinning assumption of modern legal positivism is that the question of how legal standards differ from normative standards in other spheres of human thought is resolved via the concept of a legal system and the notion of internal logic, through use of contextual definition. This approach is seen to lead to an untenable form of structuralism altogether at odds with the positivist's intentions. An alternative strategy is offered which allows the positivists to retain their deepest insights, though at a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  33
    Jurisprudence or legal science?: a debate about the nature of legal theory.Sean Coyle & George Pavlakos (eds.) - 2005 - Portland, Or.: Hart Publishing.
    In a series of new essays the authors attempt to answer important questions about the nature of jurisprudential thinking.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  36
    Reclaiming the rights of the Hobbesian subject.Sean Coyle - 2009 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 17 (1):210 – 213.
  19.  5
    The Ideality of Law.Sean Coyle - 2009 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 6 (4):521-534.
    Both of the books under review offer a challenge to the dominant jurisprudential tradition of legal positivism. Underlying this superficial similarity in aims is a sharp divergence in philosophical outlook. Whereas Dworkin's arguments operate within a body of background assumptions that he shares with his opponents, and which he has done much to shape, Simmonds sees his task as challenging those assumptions. This is particularly evident in the moral philosophies at the heart of each book: Dworkin can be seen as (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. The ideality of law?Sean Coyle - 2013 - In Thom Brooks (ed.), Law and Legal Theory. Leiden: Brill.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  8
    The Meanings of the Logical Constants in Deontic Logic.Sean Coyle - 1999 - Ratio Juris 12 (1):39-58.
    If deontic logic is to cast light on any of the normative sciences, such as legal reasoning, then certain problems regarding its logical constants must be faced. Recent studies in the area of deontic logic have tended to assume that it is our responses to the “paradoxes” of deontic implication which are fundamental to resolving problems with the use of deontic logic to investigate various branches of normative reasoning. In this paper I wish to show that the paradoxes are of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  4
    The Philosophical Foundations of Environmental Law: Property, Rights and Nature.Sean Coyle - 2004 - Hart. Edited by Karen Morrow.
    This book challenges the accepted view by arguing that environmental law must be seen not as a mere instrument of social policy, but as a historical product of ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  2
    The Possibility of Deontic Logic.Sean Coyle - 2002 - Ratio Juris 15 (3):294-318.
    A recent series of papers, sparked off by a note by Robert Walter (1996), has rekindled the debate over the possibility of creating a logic of normative concepts. The debate correctly centres on ways in which Jørgensen’s dilemma might be resolved (Jørgensen 1937–8), since a means of resolving that dilemma is the only apparently available way in which to establish that a logic of norms is possible. Two separate questions require answers: (i) what is the correct way in which to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  42
    A Review of Izhak Englard, Corrective and Distributive Justice: From Aristotle to Modern Times[REVIEW]Sean Coyle - 2011 - Jurisprudence 2 (2):597-601.
  25. Sean Coyle and Karin Morrow, The Philosophical Foundations of Environmental Law: Property Rights and Nature Reviewed by.Arlene Kwasniak - 2005 - Philosophy in Review 25 (5):336-339.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  26
    Minimalism and Normative Reasoning: A Reply to Sean Coyle.Giorgio Volpe - 2002 - Ratio Juris 15 (3):319-327.
    This paper defends the “minimalist” solution to Jørgensen’s dilemma against the objections raised by Coyle (2002). As most of these objections stem from a misconstrual of the account of truth that underlies the minimalist solution, the paper is largely an attempt to provide a clearer statement of the “minimal theory of truth,” a sharper characterization of the features that distinguish it from other deflationary views, and a careful presentation of the minimalist account of the logical role of truth–ascriptions. The (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  88
    Philosophy and Model Theory.Tim Button & Sean P. Walsh - 2018 - Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Edited by Sean Walsh & Wilfrid Hodges.
    Philosophy and model theory frequently meet one another. Philosophy and Model Theory aims to understand their interactions -/- Model theory is used in every ‘theoretical’ branch of analytic philosophy: in philosophy of mathematics, in philosophy of science, in philosophy of language, in philosophical logic, and in metaphysics. But these wide-ranging appeals to model theory have created a highly fragmented literature. On the one hand, many philosophically significant mathematical results are found only in mathematics textbooks: these are aimed squarely at mathematicians; (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  28.  32
    The Place of Philosophy in Bioethics Today.Jennifer Blumenthal-Barby, Sean Aas, Dan Brudney, Jessica Flanigan, S. Matthew Liao, Alex London, Wayne Sumner & Julian Savulescu - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 22 (12):10-21.
    In some views, philosophy’s glory days in bioethics are over. While philosophers were especially important in the early days of the field, so the argument goes, the majority of the work in bioethics today involves the “simple” application of existing philosophical principles or concepts, as well as empirical work in bioethics. Here, we address this view head on and ask: What is the role of philosophy in bioethics today? This paper has three specific aims: (1) to respond to skeptics and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  29.  37
    Suffering in the advanced cancer patient: a definition and taxonomy.Nathan I. Cherny, Nessa Coyle & Kathleen M. Foley - forthcoming - Journal of Palliative Care.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  26
    Seeing things in Merleau-ponty.Sean D. Kelly - 2004 - In Taylor Carman & Mark B. N. Hansen (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Merleau-Ponty. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 74-110.
    The passage above comes from the opening pages of Merleau-Ponty’s essay on Edmund Husserl. It proposes a risky interpretive principle. The main feature of this principle is that the seminal aspects of a thinker’s work are so close to him that he is incapable of articulating them himself. Nevertheless, these aspects pervade the work, give it its style, its sense and its direction, and therefore belong to it essentially. As Martin Heidegger writes, in a passage quoted by Merleau-Ponty: " The (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  31.  33
    The non-conceptual content of perceptual experience: Situation dependence and fineness of grain.Sean D. Kelly - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (3):601-608.
    I begin by examining a recent debate between John McDowell and Christopher Peacocke over whether the content of perceptual experience is non-conceptual. Although I am sympathetic to Peacocke’s claim that perceptual content is non-conceptual, I suggest a number of ways in which his arguments fail to make that case. This failure stems from an over-emphasis on the "fine-grainedness" of perceptual content - a feature that is relatively unimportant to its non-conceptual structure. I go on to describe two other features of (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  32.  45
    Demonstrative concepts and experience.Sean Dorrance Kelly - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (3):397-420.
    A number of authors have argued recently that the content of perceptual experience can, and even must, be characterized in conceptual terms. Their claim, more precisely, is that every perceptual experience is such that, of necessity, its content is constituted entirely by concepts possessed by the subject having the experience. This is a surprising result. For it seems reasonable to think that a subject’s experiences could be richer and more fine-grained than his conceptual repertoire; that a subject might be able, (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  33. The puzzle of temporal experience.Sean D. Kelly - 2005 - In Andrew Brook & Kathleen Akins (eds.), Cognition and the Brain: The Philosophy and Neuroscience Movement. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 208--238.
    There you are at the opera house. The soprano has just hit her high note – a glassshattering high C that fills the hall – and she holds it. She holds it. She holds it. She holds it. She holds it. She holds the note for such a long time that after a while a funny thing happens: you no longer seem only to hear it, the note as it is currently sounding, that glass-shattering high C that is loud and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  34. A cognitive neurobiological account of deception: evidence from functional neuroimaging.Sean Spence - 2006 - In Semir Zeki & Oliver Goodenough (eds.), Law and the Brain. Oxford University Press.
  35. Free will in the light of neuropsychiatry.Sean Spence - 1996 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (2):75-90.
    If the notion of free will is to be retained by philosophers, psychiatrists and psychologists, then it will be a free will which is essentially non-conscious. The purpose of this paper is to demonstrate that a conscious free will (in the sense of consciousness initiating action) is incompatible with the evidence of neuroscience, and the phenomenology described in the literature of normal creativity, psychotic passivity, and the neurological syndrome of the alien limb or hand. In particular the work of Libet (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  36.  13
    Merleau–ponty on the body.Sean Dorrance Kelly - 2002 - Ratio 15 (4):376–391.
    The French philosopher Maurice Merleau-Ponty claims that there are two distinct ways in which we can understand the place of an object when we are visually apprehending it. The first involves an intentional relation to the object that is essentially cognitive or can serve as the input to cognitive processes; the second irreducibly involves a bodily set or preparation to deal with the object. Because of its essential bodily component, Merleau-Ponty calls this second kind of understanding ‘motor intentional’. In this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  37.  12
    The normative nature of perceptual experience.Sean D. Kelly - 2010 - In Bence Nanay (ed.), Perceiving the world. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 146.
  38. Grasping at straws: Motor intentionality and the cognitive science of skillful action.Sean D. Kelly - 2000 - In Essays in Honor of Hubert Dreyfus, Vol. II. MIT Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  39.  16
    Alien control: From phenomenology to cognitive neurobiology.Sean Spence - 2001 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 8 (2-3):163-172.
    People experiencing alien control report that their thoughts, movements, actions, and emotions have been replaced by those of an "other." The latter is commonly a perceived persecutor of the patient. Here I describe the clinical phenomenology of alien control, mechanistic models that have been used to explain it, problems inherent in these models, the brain deficits and functional abnormalities associated with this symptom, and the means by which disordered agency may be examined in this perplexing condition. Our current state of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  40.  7
    Why (Almost All) Cosmologists Are Atheists.Sean Carroll - 2005 - Faith and Philosophy 22 (5):622-635.
    Science and religion both make claims about the fundamental workings of the universe. Although these claims are not a priori incompatible (we could imaginebeing brought to religious belief through scientific investigation), I will argue that in practice they diverge. If we believe that the methods of science can be used to discriminate between fundamental pictures of reality, we are led to a strictly materialist conception of the universe. While the details of modern cosmology are not a necessary part of this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  41.  32
    The Actor's Brain: Exploring the Cognitive Neuroscience of Free Will.Sean Spence - 2009 - Oxford University Press.
    Is free will just an illusion? What is it in the brain that allows us to pursue our own actions and objectives? What is it about this organ that permits seemingly purposeful behaviour, giving us the impression we are free? This book takes a journey into the brain to examine what is about known voluntary behaviour, and why it can go wrong.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  42.  53
    How to avoid unfair discrimination against disabled patients in healthcare resource allocation.Sean Sinclair - 2012 - Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (3):158-162.
    The paper proposes a new method of researching public opinion for the purposes of valuing the outcomes of healthcare interventions. The issue I address is that, under the quality-adjusted life-year system, disabled patients face a higher cost-effectiveness hurdle than able-bodied patients. This seems inequitable. The author considers the alternative approaches to valuing healthcare interventions that have been proposed, and shows that all of them face the same problem. It is proposed that to value an outcome, instead of researching the general (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  43.  10
    Towards a functional anatomy of volition.Sean A. Spence & Chris D. Frith - 1999 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 6 (8-9):8-9.
    In this paper we examine the functional anatomy of volition, as revealed by modern brain imaging techniques, in conjunction with neuropsychological data derived from human and non-human primates using other methodologies. A number of brain regions contribute to the performance of consciously chosen, or ‘willed', actions. Of particular importance is dorsolateral prefrontal cortex , together with those brain regions with which it is connected, via cortico-subcortical and cortico-cortical circuits. That aspect of free will which is concerned with the voluntary selection (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  44.  57
    Group Virtues: No Great Leap Forward with Collectivism.Sean Cordell - 2017 - Res Publica 23 (1):43-59.
    A body of work in ethics and epistemology has advanced a collectivist view of virtues. Collectivism holds that some social groups can be subjects in themselves which can possess attributes such as agency or responsibility. Collectivism about virtues holds that virtues are among those attributes. By focusing on two different accounts, I argue that the collectivist virtue project has limited prospects. On one such interpretation of institutional virtues, virtue-like features of the social collective are explained by particular group-oriented features of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  45.  21
    Quotients of strongly proper forcings and guessing models.Sean Cox & John Krueger - 2016 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 81 (1):264-283.
  46. Athenaeus of Attalia on the Psychological Causes of Bodily Health.Sean Coughlin - 2018 - In Chiara Thumiger & Peter N. Singer (eds.), Mental Illness in Ancient Medicine: From Celsus to Paul of Aegina. Studies in Ancient Medicine. pp. 107-142.
    Athenaeus of Attalia distinguishes two types of exercise or training (γυμνασία) that are required at each stage of life: training of the body and training of the soul. He says that training of the body includes activities like physical exercises, eating, drinking, bathing and sleep. Training of the soul, on the other hand, consists of thinking, education, and emotional regulation (in other words, 'philosophy'). The notion of 'training of the soul' and the contrast between 'bodily' and 'psychic' exercise is common (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47.  7
    Punishing hypocrisy: The roles of hypocrisy and moral emotions in deciding culpability and punishment of criminal and civil moral transgressors.Sean M. Laurent, Brian A. M. Clark, Stephannie Walker & Kimberly D. Wiseman - 2014 - Cognition and Emotion 28 (1):59-83.
    Three experiments explored how hypocrisy affects attributions of criminal guilt and the desire to punish hypocritical criminals. Study 1 established that via perceived hypocrisy, a hypocritical criminal was seen as more culpable and was punished more than a non-hypocritical criminal who committed an identical crime. Study 2 expanded on this, showing that negative moral emotions (anger and disgust) mediated the relationships between perceived hypocrisy, criminal guilt, and punishment. Study 3 replicated the emotion finding from Study 2 using new scenarios where (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  48. Temporal awareness.Sean Dorrance Kelly - 2005 - In David Woodruff Smith & Amie Lynn Thomasson (eds.), Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind. Oxford, GB: Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  49.  17
    Ψ-epistemic quantum cosmology?Peter W. Evans, Sean Gryb & Karim P. Y. Thébault - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 56:1-12.
    This paper provides a prospectus for a new way of thinking about the wavefunction of the universe: a Ψ-epistemic quantum cosmology. We present a proposal that, if successfully implemented, would resolve the cosmological measurement problem and simultaneously allow us to think sensibly about probability and evolution in quantum cosmology. Our analysis draws upon recent work on the problem of time in quantum gravity and causally symmet- ric local hidden variable theories. Our conclusion weighs the strengths and weaknesses of the approach (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  51
    Characterizing large cardinals in terms of layered posets.Sean Cox & Philipp Lücke - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (5):1112-1131.
1 — 50 / 1000