Results for 'Clear and distinct ideas'

998 found
Order:
  1. Clear and Distinct Ideas in Eighteenth Century Germany: Metaphysics, Logic, Aesthetics.Colin McQuillan - 2017 - In Manuel Sánchez-Rodríguez & Miguel Escribano (eds.), Leibniz en Dialogo. Seville: Themata.
  2. Clear and Distinct Perception in Descartes's Philosophy.Shoshana Smith - 2005 - Dissertation, University of California Berkeley
    (Shoshana Smith now goes by her married name, Shoshana Brassfield: http://philpapers.org/profile/37640) Descartes famously claims that everything we perceive clearly and distinctly is true. Although this rule is fundamental to Descartes’s theory of knowledge, readers from Gassendi and Leibniz onward have complained that unless Descartes can say explicitly what clear and distinct perception is, how we know when we have it, and why it cannot be wrong, then the rule is empty. I offer a detailed analysis of clear (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  6
    7. Analysis in the Meditations: The Quest for Clear and Distinct Ideas.E. M. Curley - 1986 - In Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (ed.), Essays on Descartes’ Meditations. University of California Press. pp. 153-176.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  4.  17
    Clearness and Distinctness in Descartes.Alan Gewirth - 1943 - Philosophy 18 (69):17 - 36.
    Descartes's general rule that “whatever is clearly and distinctly perceived is true” has traditionally been criticized on two closely related grounds. As Leibniz, for example, puts it, clearness and distinctness are of no value as criteria of truth unless we have criteria of clearness and distinctness; but Descartes gives none. And consequently, the standards of judgment which the rule in fact evokes are purely subjective and psychological. There must hence be set up analytic, logical “marks” by means of which it (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  5.  10
    Descartes's Early Doctrine of Clear and Distinct Ideas.Stephen Gaukroger - 1992 - Journal of the History of Ideas 53 (4):585-602.
  6.  34
    Clear and distinct perception.Sarah Patterson - 2008 - In Janet Broughton & John Carriero (eds.), A Companion to Descartes. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 216-234.
    Book synopis: A collection of more than 30 specially commissioned essays, this volume surveys the work of the 17th-century philosopher-scientist commonly regarded as the founder of modern philosophy, while integrating unique essays detailing the context and impact of his work. Covers the full range of historical and philosophical perspectives on the work of Descartes Discusses his seminal contributions to our understanding of skepticism, mind-body dualism, self-knowledge, innate ideas, substance, causality, God, and the nature of animals Explores the philosophical significance (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  7.  71
    Descartes and Husserl on “Clear and Distinct”.Haojun Zhang - 2019 - Husserl Studies 35 (1):51-72.
    The term “clear and distinct” is used by both Descartes and Husserl when they talk about the truth of an idea and the evidence of judgment. Although the words “clear” and “distinct” are juxtaposed with the conjunction “and,” this does not mean that their status is equal. If the concept of “evidence” can be used to characterize the hierarchical relationship between them, then we can say that, for Descartes, distinct evidence is higher than clear (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  24
    Objective Being and “Ofness” in Descartes.Lionel Shapiro - 2011 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 84 (2):378-418.
    It is generally assumed that Descartes invokes “objective being in the intellect” in order to explain or describe an idea’s status as being “of something.” I argue that this assumption is mistaken. As emerges in his discussion of “materially false ideas” in the Fourth Replies, Descartes recognizes two senses of ‘idea of’. One, a theoretical sense, is itself introduced in terms of objective being. Hence Descartes can’t be introducing objective being to explain or describe “ofness” understood in this sense. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  2
    Time and the Idea of Time.Oliver A. Johnson - 1989 - Hume Studies 15 (1):205-219.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:205 TIME AND THE IDEA OF TIME Hume entitled Part II of Book I of the Treatise "Of the Ideas of Space and Time." Students of this most obscure Part of the Book are aware, however, that he spends little time in it on time. The main reason for his concentration on space. is polemical. In Part II his primary object is to exhibit the contradictions and absurdities (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  19
    Reid: Conception, Representation and Innate Ideas.Roger D. Gallie - 1997 - Hume Studies 23 (2):315-336.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Studies Volume XXIII, Number 2, November 1997, pp. 315-335 Reid: Conception, Representation and Innate Ideas ROGER D. GALLIE Section I of this paper begins with a presentation of Thomas Reid's doctrine of the signification of words, of what words signify or represent. That presentation serves to introduce a problem of interpretation, namely, what Reid thinks the connection is between conceiving something and grasping what a term for (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  11.  90
    Substance, Reality, and Distinctness.Boris Hennig - 2008 - Prolegomena 7 (1):2008.
    Descartes claims that God is a substance, and that mind and body are two different and separable substances. This paper provides some background that renders these claims intelligible. For Descartes, that something is real means it can exist in separation, and something is a substance if it does not depend on other substances for its existence. Further, separable objects are correlates of distinct ideas, for an idea is distinct (in an objective sense) if its object may be (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  10
    Die Möglichkeit Gottes und die Kompossibilität von Ideen. Wie Leibniz den ontologischen Gottesbeweis Descartes’ zu verbessern versucht (Teil 1).Walter Mesch - 2017 - Studia Leibnitiana 49 (1):28.
    As is well known, Leibniz criticises Descartes for not having shown that God (considered as ens perfectissimum ) is possible, and tries to fill this gap by proving God’s possibility on the basis of absolutely positive and simple perfections. For many readers, however, these perfections have appeared problematic or unintelligible. In my paper, I primarily want to show, that they can be made comprehensible by working out their foundations in Plato’s theory of ideas. On this basis, I want to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  17
    Hume, Substance, and Causation: A Solution to a Nasty Problem.Alexander P. Bozzo - 2023 - Hume Studies 48 (2):263-282.
    Louis Loeb has identified a “nasty problem” in connection with Hume’s theory of meaning. The problem is that Hume seemingly claims we lack ideas corresponding to key metaphysical terms, such as terms like “substance” and “necessary connection,” but he then proceeds to explain why philosophers believe in the existence of entities denoted by such terms. In short, Hume seems motivated to explain belief in the existence of certain entities, despite his claiming we have no ideas corresponding to them. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  19
    Wittgenstein, Literature, and the Idea of a Practice.Peter Lamarque - 2010 - British Journal of Aesthetics 50 (4):375-388.
    The familiar idea that literature is embedded in social practices that help explain both its existence and its value took a distinctive form in analytic philosophy, drawing on speech act theory and a conception of ‘rules’. A major influence was John Rawls's seminal paper ‘Two Concepts of Rules’ (1955) in which he introduced the ‘practice conception of rules’ according to which certain practices are defined by rules that in turn make possible certain kinds of action. The idea underlies the notion (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  15. A Fundamental Ambiguity In The Cartesian Theory Of Ideas: Descartes And Leibniz On Intellectual Apprehension/ Uma Ambiguidade Fundamental Na Teoria Cartesiana Das Idéias: Descartes E Leibniz Sobre A Apreensão Intelectual.Graciela De Pierris - 2007 - Manuscrito 30 (2):383-422.
    Traditionally the modern theory of ideas has been discussed primarily in reference to its alleged introduction of a veil of mental items between the mind and the world, which leads, through the empiricists, to radical skepticism about the existence of an external world. Here I propose to emphasize an entirely different aspect of the Cartesian theory of ideas which, in my view, is more fundamental in opening the empiricist path that leads to Hume’s radical skepticism. I argue that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  8
    Descartes and the Real Distinction between Mind and Body.Daniel E. Flage - 2014 - Review of Metaphysics 68 (1):93-106.
    How does Descartes justify his claim that conceiving of a mind as a thinking thing and a body as an extended thing show that mind and body are distinct substances? The paper attempts to answer that question by following a clue Descartes gave Arnauld that virtually everything in Meditations Three through Five is germane to the real distinction between mind and body. The paper develops the distinction between material truth and formal truth from Descartes’s discussions of falsity in Meditation (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  5
    Reflexivity and the Idea of Law.N. E. Simmonds - 2010 - Jurisprudence 1 (1):1-23.
    To understand the distinctive characteristics of the institutions of law, one needs to understand the idea of law. Understanding the nature of law is not ultimately a matter of achieving a careful description of social practices but a matter of grasping the idea towards which those practices must be understood as oriented. The idea of law is the focal point that enables us to make coherent sense of the otherwise diverse features of practice, but it is not itself a matter (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  21
    Spinoza and Descartes on Expression and Ideas - Conception and Ideational Intentionality.Andrew Burnside - 2023 - Journal of Early Modern Studies 11 (2):13-29.
    I make the case that Spinoza built on Descartes’s conception of what it means for a mind to have an idea by linking it with his concept of expression because ideas express realities in terms of a causation‑conception conditional (but not vice versa). Briefly, if an idea is caused by a being, then that being is conceived through that idea. Descartes thinks of our clearly and distinctly possessing an idea as a sufficient ground for our expression of what we (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  40
    Meditations on First Philosophy: With Selections From the Objections and Replies.René Descartes - 1960 - Cambridge, England: Oxford University Press UK. Edited by John Cottingham & Bernard Williams.
    In Descartes's Meditations, one of the key texts of Western philosophy, the thinker rejects all his former beliefs in the quest for new certainties. Discovering his own existence as a thinking entity in the very exercise of doubt, he goes on to prove the existence of God, who guarantees his clear and distinct ideas as a means of access to the truth. He develops new conceptions of body and mind, capable of serving as foundations for the new (...)
  20.  27
    Spinoza and Descartes on Expression and Ideas.Andrew Burnside - 2022 - Journal of Early Modern Studies 11 (2):13-29.
    I make the case that Spinoza built on Descartes’s conception of what it means for a mind to have an idea by linking it with his concept of expression because ideas express realities in terms of a causation‑conception conditional (but not vice versa). Briefly, if an idea is caused by a being, then that being is conceived through that idea. Descartes thinks of our clearly and distinctly possessing an idea as a sufficient ground for our expression of what we (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  25
    Ideas, Evidence, and Method: Hume’s Skepticism and Naturalism Concerning Knowledge and Causation by Graciela De Pierris. [REVIEW]Angela Coventry - 2016 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 54 (4):678-680.
    De Pierris offers a reading that unites radical skepticism and normative naturalism as “two equally important and mutually complementary aspects of Hume’s philosophical position”. The “modern theory of ideas” shapes skepticism, and Newtonian methodology is the basis for naturalism. The “modern theory of ideas” holds that evidence for optimal human cognition is grounded in the “immediate acquaintance with ostensive presentations that are or have been given to the mind”. This is the “presentational-phenomenological model of apprehension”. Descartes introduces to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  36
    Spinoza and the Possibility of Adequate Ideas.Thaddeus Robinson - 2022 - Journal of Modern Philosophy 4 (1):8.
    Adequate ideas are the fundamental element of Spinoza’s epistemological program. However, a recurrent worry among scholars is that Spinoza’s account of adequate ideas is inconsistent with any finite being ever having one. As I frame it, the problem is that for Spinoza an idea is adequate in a mind only if all its causal antecedents lie within the mind as well. However, it seems there can be no finite mind for which this is true; finite minds come to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  14
    Transparency and falsity in Descartes's theory of ideas.Claudia Lorena Garcia - 1999 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 7 (3):349 – 372.
    Here I develop an interpretation of Descartes' theory of ideas which differs from the standard reading in that it incorporates a distinction between what an idea appears to represent and what it represents. I argue that this interpretation not only finds support in the texts but also is required to explain a large number of assertions in Descartes which would otherwise appear irremediably obscure or problematic. For example, in my interpretation it is not puzzling that Descartes responds to Arnauld's (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  2
    Distinctness.Clarence Bonnen & Daniel Flage - 1999 - In Rocco J. Gennaro & Charles Huenemann (eds.), New essays on the rationalists. New York: Oxford University Press.
    The paper argues that, for Descartes, an idea of x is distinct only if that idea is subsumed under an eternal truth that specifies the conditions sufficient for x to exist, where x is taken to be an entity of a particular kind. It is argued that clear and distinct ideas are materially true, i.e., pertain to possible existence. It is shown that clarity and distinctness pertain primarily to perceptions as acts, and that it is possible (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. A Fundamental Ambiguity In The Cartesian Theory Of Ideas.Graciela De Pierris - 2002 - Manuscrito 25 (2):105-146.
    Traditionally the modern theory of ideas has been discussed primarily in reference to its alleged introduction of a veil of mental items between the mind and the world, which leads, through the empiricists, to radical skepticism about the existence of an external world. Here I propose to emphasize an entirely different aspect of the Cartesian theory of ideas which, in my view, is more fundamental in opening the empiricist path that leads to Hume’s radical skepticism. I argue that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Spinoza and the problematic acquaintance with passions. [Spanish].Miguel Omar Masci - 2009 - Eidos: Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad Del Norte 9:282-311.
    Normal 0 21 false false false ES-CO X-NONE X-NONE MicrosoftInternetExplorer4 Normal 0 21 false false false ES-CO X-NONE X-NONE MicrosoftInternetExplorer4 /* Style Definitions */ table.MsoNormalTable {mso-style-name:"Tabla normal"; mso-tstyle-rowband-size:0; mso-tstyle-colband-size:0; mso-style-noshow:yes; mso-style-priority:99; mso-style-qformat:yes; mso-style-parent:""; mso-padding-alt:0cm 5.4pt 0cm 5.4pt; mso-para-margin:0cm; mso-para-margin-bottom:.0001pt; line-height:115%; mso-pagination:widow-orphan; font-size:10.0pt; font-family:"Calibri","sans-serif"; mso-fareast-font-family:Calibri; mso-bidi-font-family:CalistoMT;} Spinoza’s deductive metaphysic system states a problem in regard to the knowledge of the passions. On the one hand, the passions are explained like body’s affections, but the soul has a mutilated and confused knowledge of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  11
    Descartes and Epistemology With or Without God.Edwin Etieyibo - 2015 - Philosophia: International Journal of Philosophy (Philippine e-journal) 16 (1):65-86.
    The conventioral understanding takes God to pray a pivotal philosophical role in Descartes's epistemological project. Michael Della Rocca disagrees with this interpretation. In a recent article, " Descartes, the Cartesian Circle, and epistemology without God," he forcefully argues for the view that takes God to be peripheral and at the fringe of Descartes's account of knowledge. He argues that Descartes renders God less important in his epistemology simply in virtue of having normative certainty of clear and distinct (...) or perceptions prior to his theological argument. This paper generally argues that although it could be said that Descartes has normative certainty of some claims before his arguments for God's existence, it is misleading to claim that God plays no pivotal philosophical role in Descartes's epistemological project. In particular, it argues that since the relevant conditions for scientia for Descartes include normative certainty of clear and distinct perceptions and understanding of the metaphysical foundations of cognition it is mistaken to suppose that God takes on a less than central role in Descartes's epistemology. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Clear and Distinct Perception in the Stoics, Augustine, and William of Ockham.Tamer Nawar - 2022 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 96 (1):185-207.
    There is a long history of philosophers granting a privileged epistemic status to cognition of directly present objects. In this paper, I examine three important historic accounts which provide different models of this cognitive state and its connection with its objects: that of the Stoics, who are corporealists and think that ordinary perception may have an epistemically privileged status, but who seem to struggle to accommodate non-perceptual cognizance; that of Augustine, who thinks that incorporeal objects are directly present to us (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  25
    Descartes, the cartesian circle, and epistemology without God.Michael Della Rocca - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (1):1–33.
    This paper defends an interpretation of Descartes according to which he sees us as having normative (and not merely psychological) certainty of all clear and distinct ideas during the period in which they are apprehended clearly and distinctly. However, on this view, a retrospective doubt about clear and distinct ideas is possible. This interpretation allows Descartes to avoid the Cartesian Circle in an effective way and also shows that Descartes is surprisingly, in some respects, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  30. Contemporary Epistemology and the Cartesian Circle.Daniel Dohrn - 2005 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 8.
    Descartes wants to show that clear and distinct ideas are trustworthy. However, his argument seems circular. For his premise that God is trustworthy depends on clear and distinct insight. Descartes’ reaction to the circularity reproach can be interpreted in two ways. The first is a psychological one. Clear and distinct insights are coercing. Thus they cannot be doubted as long as one attends to them. The argument is only meant to extend this instantaneous (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Clearness and Distinctness in Descartes.Alan Gewirth - 1986 - In John Cottingham (ed.), Descartes. New York: Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  32.  10
    Presentations and evaluations: A new look at Husserl's distinction between objectifying and non‐objectifying acts.Andrea Sebastiano Staiti - forthcoming - European Journal of Philosophy.
    In this paper, I take a fresh look at Husserl's key distinction between objectifying and non‐objectifying acts, which roughly amounts to a distinction between presentational and evaluative experiences. My goal is to provide a clear and unified reconstruction of Husserl's argument for the thesis that non‐objectifying acts are necessarily founded in objectifying acts, a thesis that is highly controversial in and beyond Husserlian scholarship. In the first section, I reconstruct Husserl's view in the Logical Investigations, according to which only (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Being-in-a-Situation, and the Critique of Traditional Philosophy, in the Thought of Gabriel Marcel.Brendan Sweetman - 1992 - Dissertation, University of Southern California
    This is a study of Marcel's valuable and unique contribution to contemporary epistemology, which originated out of his existentialist critique of traditional Cartesian philosophy. Marcel argues that Descartes conceives the self as a discrete entity, distinct from the body, which "looks out" upon the external world, and apprehends it by means of clear and distinct ideas, ideas which can be understood without reference to the world. This view motivated Descartes's epistemological project, and the project of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Self-knowledge in Descartes and Malebranche.Lawrence Nolan & John Whipple - 2005 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 43 (1):55-81.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 43.1 (2005) 55-81 [Access article in PDF] Self-Knowledge in Descartes and Malebranche Lawrence Nolan John Whipple 1. Introduction Descartes's notorious claim that mind is better known than body has been the target of repeated criticisms, but none appears more challenging than that of his intellectual heir Nicolas Malebranche.1 Whereas other critics—especially twentieth-century philosophers eager to use Descartes as their whipping boy—have often been (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  35.  46
    Descartes’s Theory of Distinction.Paul Hoffman - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (1):57-78.
    In the first part of this paper I explore the relations among distinctness, separability, number, and non-identity. I argue that Descartes believes plurality in things themselves arises from distinction, so that things distinct in any of the three ways are not identical. The only exception concerns universals which, considered in things themselves, are identical to particulars. I also argue that to be distinct is to be separable. Things distinct by reason are separable only in thought by means (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  36.  15
    The Distinction of Ordinary (‘Awām) and Elite (Khawāṣ) People in Islamic Thought.Emine Taşçi̇ Yildirim - 2020 - Cumhuriyet İlahiyat Dergisi 24 (2):665-685.
    Distinction of ‘awām- khawāṣ (the ordinary and the elite) is a general distinction in philosophical literature that shows the difference of people in their level of understanding the truth. It is possible to take this distinction back to Plato in Ancient Greek philosophy. Plato's hesitation in expressing his philosophical thoughts in written form, and Aristotle's use of obscure expressions and symbols in his works against the possibility of reaching those who are not competent, is a result of the distinction between (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  19
    Hume Against Spinoza and Aristotle.Frank J. Leavitt - 1991 - Hume Studies 17 (2):203-208.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Against Spinoza and Aristotle1 Frank J. Leavitt It is always good to try to make peace, to try to resolve differences between whatsomebelieveare conflictingpoints ofview. Nevertheless, sometimes the points ofview which are believed to be opposed to each other really do oppose one another and so the most ingenious attempts at reconciliation turn out to have been ill-conceived. Wim Klever has brought considerable scholarship to bear in his (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  30
    Locke's way of ideas as context for his theory of education in Of the Conduct of the Understanding.Paul Schuurman - 2001 - History of European Ideas 27 (1):45-59.
    The central theme of John Locke's Of the Conduct of the Understanding is human error. The Conduct was conceived as an additional chapter to An Essay concerning Understanding, but it was never finished and published posthumously in 1706 as a separate work. Modern authors have regarded the Conduct as an educational treatise. Indeed, the analysis in this work of the nature and causes of error and the ways to prevent and remedy error gives rise to numerous educational reflections. However, the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  97
    Hume on Thick and Thin Causation.Alexander Bozzo - 2018 - Dissertation, Marquette University
    Hume is known for his claim that our idea of causation is nothing beyond constant conjunction, and that our idea of necessary connection is nothing beyond a felt determination of the mind. In short, Hume endorses a "thin" conception of causation and necessary connection. In recent years, however, a sizeable number of philosophers have come to view Hume as someone who believes in the existence of thick causal connections - that is, causal connections that allow one to infer a priori (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  6
    Logic and the classical theory of mind.Peter Novak - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (4):389-434.
    I extract several common assumptions in the Classical Theory of Mind (CTM) - mainly of Locke and Descartes - and work out a partial formalisation of the logic implicit in CTM. I then define the modal (logical) properties and relations of propositions, including the modality of conditional propositions and the validity of argument, according to the principles of CTM: that is, in terms of clear and distinct ideas, and without any reference to either possible worlds, or deducibility (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  4
    Mechanism and fracture in cartesian physics.Mark Wilson - 1997 - Topoi 16 (2):141-152.
    I'm scarcely the only reader who has found it puzzling that the self-consistent author of the Meditations, with his firm faith that God has supplied us with clear and distinct ideas sufficient to understand the material world, could have been satisfied with the messy jumble of physical doctrine we seem to find in his ~Priuci les. For example, although Descartes seems to be committed to a relationalism of some sort, his notorious laws of impact look as if (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  12
    Cross-count identity, distinctness, and the theory of internal and external relations.Ian Underwood - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 151 (2):265 - 283.
    Baxter (Australas J Philos 79: 449-464, 2001) proposes an ingenious solution to the problem of instantiation based on his theory of cross-count identity. His idea is that where a particular instantiates a universal it shares an aspect with that universal. Both the particular and the universal are numerically identical with the shared aspect in different counts. Although Baxter does not say exactly what a count is, it appears that he takes ways of counting as mysterious primitives against which different numerical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43.  6
    Descartes and Method: A Search for a Method in Meditations (review).Patrick R. Frierson - 2000 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 38 (3):436-437.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Descartes and Method: A Search for a Method in MeditationsPatrick FriersonDaniel E. Flage and Clarence A. Bonnen. Descartes and Method: A Search for a Method in Meditations. New York: Routledge, 1999. Pp. 332. Cloth, $90.00.The book has two parts. The first (Chapters 1-3 and an appendix) outlines Descartes's method of analysis, a method for discovering laws and clarifying ideas. The second (Chapters 4-10) offers a running commentary (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Clear and Distinct Perception.Sarah Patterson - 2008 - In . Blackwell. pp. 216-234.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45. Self Knowledge and the Rule of Truth.Thomas C. Vinci - 1998 - In Cartesian truth. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Basic Cartesian intuitions are directed at simple natures, not truths; but intuitions are also a foundation for propositional knowledge. There are two basic objectives of this chapter: to show how Descartes gets from intuitions to propositional knowledge, and to show how his solution to this problem structures his thinking on the main issues in Cartesian epistemology. I maintain that the solution to is to be found in the principle if we perceive the presence of an attribute A, there must be (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. On Clear and Confused Ideas: An Essay About Substance Concepts.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 2000 - Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Written by one of today's most creative and innovative philosophers, Ruth Garrett Millikan, this book examines basic empirical concepts; how they are acquired, how they function, and how they have been misrepresented in the traditional philosophical literature. Millikan places cognitive psychology in an evolutionary context where human cognition is assumed to be an outgrowth of primitive forms of mentality, and assumed to have 'functions' in the biological sense. Of particular interest are her discussions of the nature of abilities as different (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   209 citations  
  47.  15
    Recognizing clear and distinct perceptions.James M. Humber - 1981 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 41 (4):487-507.
  48.  22
    How to Make the Passions Active: Spinoza and R.G. Collingwood.Alexander Douglas - 2019 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 85:237-249.
    Most early modern philosophers held that our emotions are always passions: to experience an emotion is to undergo something rather than to do something. Spinoza is different; he holds that our emotions – what he calls our ‘affects’ – can be actions rather than passions. Moreover, we can convert a passive affect into an active one simply by forming a clear and distinct idea of it. This theory is difficult to understand. I defend the interpretation R.G. Collingwood gives (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  10
    Rethinking the Machine Metaphor Since Descartes: On the Irreducibility of Bodies, Minds, and Meanings.Charles Lowney - 2011 - Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 31 (3):179-192.
    Michael Polanyi’s conceptions of tacit knowing and emergent being are used to correct a reductionism that developed from, or reacted against, the excesses of several Cartesian assumptions: (a) the method of universal doubt; (b) the emphasis on reductive analysis to unshakeable foundations, via connections between clear and distinct ideas; (c) the notion that what is real are the basic atomic substances out of which all else is composed; (d) a sharp body-mind substance dualism; and (e) the notion (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  11
    Cartesian Dualism: An Evaluation of Wireduan and Gilbert Ryle's Refutations.Samuel Olusegun Steven - 2011 - Kritike 5 (2):156-165.
    This paper takes a philosophical look at how the views of Gilbert Ryle and Kwasi Wiredu can be used to resolving the mind-body problem located in Rene Descartes’ philosophy. The common sense account of the mind-body theory was first systematically carried out by Descartes. To him, mind and body do not only exist, they also interact. Through his notion of clear and distinct ideas, Descartes infers the existence of the mind as a thinking substance. Unlike the mind, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 998