Results for 'Homonyms'

131 found
Order:
  1.  33
    Homonyms and synonyms as retrieval cues.Leah L. Light - 1972 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 96 (2):255.
  2.  40
    Visible homonyms are ambiguous, subliminal homonyms are not: A close look at priming.Doris Eckstein, Matthias Kubat & Walter J. Perrig - 2011 - Consciousness and Cognition 20 (4):1327-1343.
    Homonyms, i.e. ambiguous words like ‘score’, have different meanings in different contexts. Previous research indicates that all potential meanings of a homonym are first accessed in parallel before one of the meanings is selected in a competitive race. If these processes are automatic, these processes of selection should even be observed when homonyms are shown subliminally. This study measured the time course of subliminal and supraliminal priming by homonyms with a frequent and a rare meaning in a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  64
    Suppressing Synonymy with a Homonym: The Emergence of the Nomenclatural Type Concept in Nineteenth Century Natural History.Joeri Witteveen - 2016 - Journal of the History of Biology 49 (1):135-189.
    ‘Type’ in biology is a polysemous term. In a landmark article, Paul Farber (Journal of the History of Biology 9(1): 93–119, 1976) argued that this deceptively plain term had acquired three different meanings in early nineteenth century natural history alone. ‘Type’ was used in relation to three distinct type concepts, each of them associated with a different set of practices. Important as Farber’s analysis has been for the historiography of natural history, his account conceals an important dimension of early nineteenth (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  4.  13
    Homonyms as items in verbal discrimination learning and transfer.Donald H. Kausler & Richard D. Olson - 1969 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 82 (1p1):136.
  5. Rechoreographing Homonymous Partners: Rancière's Dance Education from Loïe Fuller.Joshua M. Hall - 2022 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 56 (3):44-62.
    Contemporary philosopher Jacques Rancière has been criticized for a conception of “politics” that is insensitive to the diminished agency of the corporeally oppressed. In a recent article, Dana Mills locates a solution to this alleged problem in Rancière most recent book translated into English, Aisthesis, in its chapter on Mallarmé’s writings on modern dancer Loïe Fuller. My first section argues that Mills’ reading exacerbates an “homonymy” (Rancière’s term) in Rancière’s use of the word “inscription,” which means for him either a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Primary Substances and Their Homonyms in Aristotle’s Teleology.Mikolaj Domaradzki - 2018 - Diametros (58):2-17.
    The purpose of this article is to reconstruct Aristotle’s distinction between primary substances and their homonyms. It is shown that the Stagirite regards both body parts and artefacts as mere homonyms of primary substances when they are no longer capable of performing their function (ergon) and actualizing their end (telos). In the course of the present discussion, Aristotle’s approach is confronted with his famous doctrine of the four causes, whilst an analysis of the examples given by the Stagirite (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Homonymous mistakes with ontological aspirations: The persisting problem with the word 'consciousness'.Rodrigo Becerra - 2004 - Sorites 15 (December):11-23.
    In order to understand consciousness one would benefit from developing a more eclectic intellectual style. Consciousness is, as proposed by almost everyone except the stubborn reductionists, a truly mysterious concept. Its study and dissection merits a multidisciplinary approach. Waving this multidisciplinary flag has positively enlarged the discussion and neurologists, psychiatrists, mathematicians, and so on, have moved to the philosophy of mind arena, first with caution and now with a more powerful voice. Identifying what we mean by consciousness is a first (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  9
    La distinction des fabricants homonymes sur les timbres amphoriques grecs.Yvon Garlan - 2012 - Bulletin de Correspondance Hellénique 136 (1):319-338.
    Distinguishing homonymous producers on Greek amphora stamps. Among the producers associated on Greek amphora stamps with an eponymous magistrate (and having thus been in office together during a specific year) there appear rather often (up to 15% of the cases) homonyms. One may thus be surprised that the specialists have never studied the ways that the different production centres distinguished them, in a system of stamping which — whatever its ultimate purpose — must have exercised a certain control (of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  24
    Recognition of words and homonyms as a function of amount of preexposure.Donald Keller & Murray Glanzer - 1969 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 80 (1):160.
  10.  27
    Is Human a Homonym for Aristotle?Julie K. Ward - 2008 - Apeiron 41 (3):75-98.
  11.  3
    Mechanisms of homonym transformations: on Catholic variants of Stalinist discourse in Poland.Jakub Sadowski - 2022 - Semiotica 2022 (247):115-138.
    Despite its anti-religious character, totalitarian discourse, in the years 1949–1956 filling the entire space of Polish official culture, had its Catholic segment. Within this segment, there occurred a transformation of the religious net of concepts into semantic units of totalitarian language, a transformation of Catholic worldview narratives into Stalinist ones. This text aims to describe the semiotic mechanisms of such transformation. The relations between the initial semiosphere of language and the sub-semiosphere of its totalitarian variant are described. Presented here is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  14
    The synonymy of homonyms.Kevin L. Flannery - 1999 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 81 (3):268-289.
  13.  99
    Antiphasis as Homonym in Aristotle.Robert Laurence Gallagher - 2014 - History and Philosophy of Logic 35 (4):317-331.
    Antiphasis is a case of core-dependent homonymy, and has three significations in Aristotle's philosophy: antiphasis as an opposition between propositions ; antiphasis as the opposition between ‘subject’ and ‘not a subject’ in coming-to-be and perishing ; and antiphasis as the opposition between possession and privation . Argument based on the fifth type of priority described in Cat. 12 shows that, for Aristotle, the ontological significations are prior to the propositional.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  20
    Apparent movement in relation to homonymous and heteronymous stimulation of the cerebral hemispheres.J. A. Gengerelli - 1948 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 38 (5):592.
  15.  33
    Action dynamics reveal two types of cognitive flexibility in a homonym relatedness judgment task.Maja Dshemuchadse, Tobias Grage & Stefan Scherbaum - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  25
    How can striate vision contribute to the detection of objects within a homonymous visual field defect?Otmar Meienberg - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):455.
  17. Aristotle's "is said in many ways" and its relationship to his homonyms.Jurgis Brakas - 2011 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 49 (2):135-159.
    Being, Aristotle tells us, "is said in many ways ". So are the good and many other fundamental things. Fair enough, but what on earth does this mean? What, to narrow the focus to the basic question, does Aristotle mean by in phrases such as and other constructions where is used in the same sense? While scholars have presented us with an array of different translations for this difficult term, not all of them are compatible and none seem adequate. Yet (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  17
    Word-meaning priming extends beyond homonyms.Adam J. Curtis, Matthew H. C. Mak, Shuang Chen, Jennifer M. Rodd & M. Gareth Gaskell - 2022 - Cognition 226 (C):105175.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Aristotle’s semiotic triangles and pyramids.John Corcoran - 2015 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 21 (1):198-9.
    Imagine an equilateral triangle “pointing upward”—its horizontal base under its apex angle. A semiotic triangle has the following three “vertexes”: (apex) an expression, (lower-left) one of the expression’s conceptual meanings or senses, and (lower-right) the referent or denotation determined by the sense [1, pp. 88ff]. One example: the eight-letter string ‘coleslaw’ (apex), the concept “coleslaw” (lower-left), and the salad coleslaw (lower-right) [1, p. 84f]. Using Church’s terminology [2, pp. 6, 41]—modifying Frege’s—the word ‘coleslaw’ expresses the concept “coleslaw”, the word ‘coleslaw’ (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Aristotle on Homonymy: Dialectic and Science.Julie K. Ward - 2007 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Julie K. Ward examines Aristotle's thought regarding how language informs our views of what is real. First she places Aristotle's theory in its historical and philosophical contexts in relation to Plato and Speusippus. Ward then explores Aristotle's theory of language as it is deployed in several works, including Ethics, Topics, Physics, and Metaphysics, so as to consider its relation to dialectical practice and scientific explanation as Aristotle conceived it.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  21. Teorii︠a︡ leksicheskoĭ i grammaticheskoĭ omonimii.L. V. Malakhovskiĭ - 1990 - Leningrad: "Nauka," Leningradskoe otd-nie. Edited by R. G. Piotrovskiĭ.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Homonymy in Aristotle.Terrence Irwin - 1981 - Review of Metaphysics 34 (3):523 - 544.
    ARISTOTLE often claims that words are "homonymous" or "multivocal". He claims this about some of the crucial words and concepts of his own philosophy—"cause," "being," "one," "good," "justice," "friendship." Often he claims it with a polemical aim; other philosophers have wrongly overlooked homonymy and supposed that the same word is always said in the same way. Plato made this mistake; his accounts of being, good, and friendship are rejected because they neglect homonymy and multivocity. In Aristotle’s view Plato shared the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  23.  29
    Plotinus’ Unaffectable Soul.Christopher Noble - 2016 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 51:231-281.
    In Ennead 3.6, Plotinus maintains that the soul is unaffectable. This thesis is widely taken to imply that his soul is exempt from change and free from emotional ‘affections’. Yet these claims are difficult to reconcile with evidence that Plotinian souls acquire dispositional states, such as virtues, and are subjects of emotional ‘affections’, such as anger. This paper offers an alternative account that aims to address these difficulties. In denying affections to soul, Plotinus is offering a distinction between the soul’s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  24. What is Conceptual Engineering and What Should it Be?David Chalmers - 2020 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 63.
    Conceptual engineering is the design, implementation, and evaluation of concepts. Conceptual engineering includes or should include de novo conceptual engineering (designing a new concept) as well as conceptual re-engineering (fixing an old concept). It should also include heteronymous (different-word) as well as homonymous (same-word) conceptual engineering. I discuss the importance and the difficulty of these sorts of conceptual engineering in philosophy and elsewhere.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  25.  77
    Contextualism and Polysemy.François Recanati - 2017 - Dialectica 71 (3):379-397.
    In this paper, I argue that that polysemy is a two-sided phenomenon. It can be reduced neither to pragmatic modulation nor to ambiguity, for it is a mixture of both. The senses of a polysemous expression result from pragmatic modulation but they are stored in memory, as the senses of an ambiguous expression are. The difference with straightforward ambiguity is that the modulation relations between the senses are transparent to the language users: the senses are felt as related – they (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  26. Deflationary representation, inference, and practice.Mauricio Suárez - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 49 (C):36-47.
    This paper defends the deflationary character of two recent views regarding scientific representation, namely RIG Hughes’ DDI model and the inferential conception. It is first argued that these views’ deflationism is akin to the homonymous position in discussions regarding the nature of truth. There, we are invited to consider the platitudes that the predicate “true” obeys at the level of practice, disregarding any deeper, or more substantive, account of its nature. More generally, for any concept X, a deflationary approach is (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  27.  2
    Omonimii︠a︡: aspektolohii︠a︡, problematyka: filolohichna rozvidka z leksykolohiï ta stylistyky.Hanna Ivanivna Kuzʹmenko - 2000 - Kyïv: Vydavnychyĭ t︠s︡entr "Kyïvsʹkyĭ universytet".
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  19
    Wokół homonimii międzyjęzykowej.Małgorzata Majewska (ed.) - 2017 - Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe Uniwersytetu Kardynała Stefana Wyszyńskiego.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  7
    Exhortation à la philosophie: le dossier grec, Aristote.Sophie van der Meeren, Aristotle & Iamblichus (eds.) - 2011 - Paris: Belles lettres.
    " Il faut philosopher " : cette formule se rencontre en diverses oeuvres de l'Antiquité destinées à exhorter un public à pratiquer la sagesse ou la philosophie, et, en particulier, dans certains des rares témoignages sur le Protreptique d'Aristote désormais perdu. Plusieurs philologues, à partir de la fin du me siècle, crurent retrouver un vaste ensemble de " fragments " de celui-ci dans l'ouvrage homonyme du néoplatonicien Jamblique. Cette " découverte " déboucha sur de nombreux travaux autour de l'authenticité aristotélicienne (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30. Words on Kripke’s Puzzle.Maciej Tarnowski & Maciej Głowacki - 2022 - Synthese 200 (4):1-21.
    In this paper we present a solution to Saul Kripke’s Puzzle About Belief Meaning and use, Dordrecht, 1979) based on Kaplan’s metaphysical picture of words. Although it is widely accepted that providing such a solution was one of the main incentives for the development of Kaplan’s theory, it was never presented by Kaplan in a systematic manner and was regarded by many as unsatisfactory. We agree with these critiques, and develop an extension of Kaplan’s theory by introducing the notion of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31. The dialectic of life.Christopher Shields - 2012 - Synthese 185 (1):103-124.
    In the dialectic of debates about the extension of life, one witnesses a predictably repeating pattern: one side appeals to a motley of variegated criteria for something’s qualifying as a living system, only to find an opposite side taking issue with the individual necessity or collective sufficiency of the proposed criteria. Some of these criteria tend to cluster with one another, while others do not: metabolism, growth and reproduction; self-organization and homeostasis; an ability to decrease internal entropy by the appropriation (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  32. Aristotle's Causal Definitions of the Soul.Cameron F. Coates - forthcoming - Ancient Philosophy.
    Does Aristotle offer a definition of the soul? In fact, he rejects the possibility of defining the soul univocally. Because “life” is a homonymous concept, so too is “soul”. Given the specific causal role that Aristotle envisages for form and essence, the soul requires multiple different definitions to capture how it functions as a cause in each form of life. Aristotle suggests demonstrations can be given which express these causal definitions; I reconstruct these demonstrations in the paper.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  5
    Rechevye vozmozhnosti tekstovoĭ omonimii.Olʹga Alekseevna Lapteva - 1999 - Moskva: IKAR.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Indexinames.Alberto Voltolini - 1995 - In J. Hill & P. Kot'attko (eds.), Karlovy Vary Studies in Reference and Meaning. Filosofia. pp. 258-285.
    Insofar as the so-called new theory of reference has come to be acknowleged as the leading theoretical paradigm in semantic research, it has been widely accepted that proper names directly refer to their designation. In advancing some of the most convincing arguments in favour of this view of names, S. Kripke has however left somehow undecided what the role of context is in determining which is the direct referent for a name. According to one interpretation of his thought, context has (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  35.  19
    Probing Lexical Ambiguity: Word Vectors Encode Number and Relatedness of Senses.Barend Beekhuizen, Blair C. Armstrong & Suzanne Stevenson - 2021 - Cognitive Science 45 (5):e12943.
    Lexical ambiguity—the phenomenon of a single word having multiple, distinguishable senses—is pervasive in language. Both the degree of ambiguity of a word (roughly, its number of senses) and the relatedness of those senses have been found to have widespread effects on language acquisition and processing. Recently, distributional approaches to semantics, in which a word's meaning is determined by its contexts, have led to successful research quantifying the degree of ambiguity, but these measures have not distinguished between the ambiguity of words (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  19
    Predication.Walter Kintsch - 2001 - Cognitive Science 25 (2):173-202.
    In Latent Semantic Analysis (LSA) the meaning of a word is represented as a vector in a high‐dimensional semantic space. Different meanings of a word or different senses of a word are not distinguished. Instead, word senses are appropriately modified as the word is used in different contexts. In N‐VP sentences, the precise meaning of the verb phrase depends on the noun it is combined with. An algorithm is described to adjust the meaning of a predicate as it is applied (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  37.  24
    Complex Pleasure: Forms of Feeling in German Literature.Stanley Corngold - 1998 - Stanford University Press.
    Complex Pleasure deals with questions of literary feeling in eight major German writers—Lessing, Kant, Hölderlin, Nietzsche, Musil, Kafka, Trakl, and Benjamin. On the basis of close readings of these authors Stanley Corngold makes vivid the following ideas: that where there is literature there is complex pleasure; that this pleasure is complex because it involves the impression of a disclosure; that this thought is foremost in the minds of a number of canonical writers; that important literary works in the German tradition—fiction, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. A contribution to the study of byzantine prosopography: The byzantine family of opoi.Stavros G. Georgiou - 2008 - Byzantion 78:224-238.
    In this study we examine the information in the sources concerning the Byzantine family of Opoi in the eleventh and twelfth centuries. According to the sources, the Opoi were an important family in that period. Although they did not belong to the major aristocratic families, many of them were distinguished in the military administration of the Empire, such as Constantine Opos during the reign of Romanos III Argyros and Michael IV Paphlagon , the homonymous officer of Alexios I Komnenos , (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  20
    Autour de l’Oedipus chymicus.Anne-Lise Rey - 2008 - Methodos 8.
    À partir de la comparaison entre l’Oedipus chymicus de Leibniz écrit en 1710 et ce qui nous a semblé un possible référent, le texte homonyme de J.J Becher de 1664, l’article s’efforce de déterminer les raisons de l’attrait que Leibniz éprouve pour la chimie de son temps. Si les pratiques de codage et de décodage de la démarche alchimique ainsi que l’attention portée aux transformations des états de la matière constituent indéniablement des points de convergence avec la philosophie leibnizienne, il (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  57
    A deflationary account of information in biology.John S. Wilkins - unknown
    An oft-repeated claim is that there is information in some biological entity or process, most especially in genes. Some of these claims derive from the Central Dogma, population genetics, and the neo-Darwinian program. Others derive from attacks upon evolution, in an attempt to show that “information cannot be created” by natural selection. In this paper I will try to show that the term “information” is a homonym for a range of distinct notions, and that these notions are either of concrete (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Conscious Unity from the Top Down: A Brentanian Approach.Anna Giustina - 2017 - The Monist 100 (1):16-37.
    The question of the unity of consciousness is often treated as the question of how different conscious experiences are related to each other in order to be unified. Many contemporary views on the unity of consciousness are based on this bottom-up approach. In this paper I explore an alternative, top-down approach, according to which (to a first approximation) a subject undergoes one single conscious experience at a time. From this perspective, the problem of unity of consciousness becomes rather the problem (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  42. How to Think about Zeugmatic Oddness.Michelle Liu - forthcoming - Review of Philosophy and Psychology:1-24.
    Zeugmatic oddness is a linguistic intuition of oddness with respect to an instance of zeugma, i.e. a sentence containing an instance of a homonymous or polysemous word being used in different meanings or senses simultaneously. Zeugmatic oddness is important for philosophical debates as philosophers often use it to argue that a particular philosophically interesting expression is ambiguous and that the phenomenon referred to by the expression is disunified. This paper takes a closer look at zeugmatic oddness. Focusing on relevant psycholinguistic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  78
    Aristotle's Causal Pluralism.Nathanael Stein - 2011 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 93 (2):121-147.
    Central to Aristotle's metaphysics and epistemology is the claim that ‘aitia’ – ‘cause’ – is “said in many ways”, i.e., multivocal. Though the importance of the four causes in Aristotle's system cannot be overstated, the nature of his pluralism about aitiai has not been addressed. It is not at all obvious how these modes of causation are related to one another, or why they all deserve a common term. Nor is it clear, in particular, whether the causes are related to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  44.  30
    Bandpass characteristics of high-frequency sensitivity and visual experience in blindsight.Doerthe Seifert, Christine Falter, Hans Strasburger & Mark A. Elliott - 2010 - Consciousness and Cognition 19 (1):144-151.
    Patient RP suffers a unilateral right homonymous quadrant anopia but demonstrates better than chance discrimination for stimuli presented in the blind field at temporal frequencies between 33 and 47 Hz . Examination of her reports of visual experience during blind-field discrimination suggests a more complex picture in which experiences particular to correct discrimination are not found at low-mid-gamma frequencies, but are significantly more likely than average at a lower frequency at which blindsight is not observed. We believe that visual experience (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  14
    Quotations as pictures.Josef Stern - 2021 - Cambridge: The MIT Press.
    The proposal of a semantics for quotations using explanatory notions drawn from philosophical theories of pictures. In Quotations as Pictures, Josef Stern develops a semantics for quotations using explanatory notions drawn from philosophical theories of pictures. He offers the first sustained analysis of the practice of quotation proper, as opposed to mentioning. Unlike other accounts that treat quotation as mentioning, Quotations as Pictures argues that the two practices have independent histories, that they behave differently semantically, that the inverted commas employed (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  68
    Homonymy in Aristotle and Speusippus.Jonathan Barnes - 1971 - Classical Quarterly 21 (01):65-.
    ‘There are important differences between Aristotle's account of homonymy and synonymy on the one hand, and Speusippus' on the other; in particular, Aristotle treated homonymy and synonymy as properties of things, whereas Speusippus treated them as properties of words. Despite this difference, in certain significant passages Aristotle fell under the influence of Speusippus and used die words “homonymous” and “synonymous” in their Speusippan senses.’.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47.  42
    Testimony and Engagement: On the Four Elements of Witnessing.Gert-Jan van der Heiden - 2021 - Studia Phaenomenologica 21:21-39.
    In order to develop a hermeneutic-phenomenological analysis of testimony, this essay will first argue that testimony is “said in many ways” without being homonymous and that contemporary epistemological approaches to testimony are not capable of accounting for all paradigmatic forms of testimony. Second, it is argued, following and extending the work of Paul Ricoeur, that by emphasizing the sense of engagement or Bezogenheit as a basic characteristic of testimony, we may find another approach to testimony that offers a phenomenological alternative (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. Curing Hitchcock’s Vertigo: A Second Dance with Rancière.Joshua M. Hall - forthcoming - Tábano. Translated by Leandro Cuellar.
    Building on my previous exploration of the role of dance in the contemporary French political philosopher Jacques Rancière’s Aisthesis: Scenes from the Aesthetic Regime of Art, first published in French in 2011, the present essay turns to another book originally published in the same year, The Intervals of Cinema. Having previously established that the core of Rancière’s philosophical method is an analysis of philosophical homonyms into figurative dancing conceptual partners, I begin by applying that method to the first chapter (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  29
    Antígona de Jean Anouilh: Convergencias y divergencias desde el punto de vista de la obra de Sófocles.María Inés Saravia de Grossi - 2015 - Circe de Clásicos y Modernos 19 (1):59-75.
    Este artículo compara las secuencias compositivas de la Antígona del escritor Jean Anouilh en relación con la pieza homónima de Sófocles. Se analizan las confluencias y los aspectos divergentes entre los personajes protagónicos y secundarios de ambas creaciones y se menciona la función del coro. Finalmente se exponen las conclusiones, y se subraya el tono fundamentalista que el personaje de Creón adquiere en el final de la obra. This article compares the compositional sequences of the Jean Anouilh's Antigone in relation (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  10
    La teoria schmittiana del grande spazio: una prospettiva post-statuale?Scalone Antonino - 2017 - Scienza and Politica. Per Una Storia Delle Dottrine 29 (56).
    The article analyses some aspects of Schmitt’s theories on international law, in particular the notion of Gro ß raum. The assumption is that with this notion Schmitt tries to re-think politics and international relations beyond the classical categories of the State. From this point of view, there is an essential affinity between the concept of politics explained in the homonymous essay published in 1927 and the concept of Gro ß raum. After the Second World War, Schmitt distances himself from the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 131