Results for 'Jim Jose'

(not author) ( search as author name )
982 found
Order:
  1.  5
    Explicating the conception of political obligation embedded in Martin Heidegger’s early treatises.William J. Wallace & Jim Jose - forthcoming - Comparative and Continental Philosophy.
    The concept of political obligation has not attracted much attention within Heideggerian scholarship. In this paper, we identify and explicate Heidegger’s conception of political obligation embedded in his pre-Kehre works. It will be argued that Heidegger’s magnum opus Being and Time and his address as Rector of Freiburg contain a latent associative account of political obligation. We argue that the ontological framework disclosed in Being and Time and the more concrete policy prescriptions of the Rectoral Address reveal a communitarian ethos (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  22
    Contesting Patrilineal Descent in Political Theory: James Mill and Nineteenth-Century Feminism.Jim Jose - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (1):151-174.
    Liberal philosopher James Mill has been understood as being unambiguously antifeminist. However, Terence Ball, supposedly informed by a feminist perspective, has argued for a new interpretation. Ball has reconceptualized Mill as a feminist and the sole source of the feminism of his son, suggesting a revision of the received wisdom about their relationship to the development of nineteenth century feminist thought. This paper takes issue with Ball's “new interpretation” and its presumed feminist basis.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3.  71
    Contesting patrilineal descent in political theory: James mill and nineteenth-century feminism.Jim Jose - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (1):151-174.
    : Liberal philosopher James Mill has been understood as being unambiguously antifeminist. However, Terence Ball, supposedly informed by a feminist perspective, has argued for a new interpretation. Ball has reconceptualized Mill as a feminist and the sole source of the feminism of his son (J. S. Mill), suggesting a revision of the received wisdom about their relationship to the development of nineteenth century feminist thought. This paper takes issue with Ball's "new interpretation" and its presumed feminist basis.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  46
    No more like pallas Athena: Displacing patrilineal accounts of modern feminist political theory.Jim Jose - 2004 - Hypatia 19 (4):1-22.
    : The history of modern feminist political theories is often framed in terms of the already existing theories of a number of radical nineteenth-century men philosophers such as James Mill, John Stuart Mill, Charles Fourier, Karl Marx, and Friedrich Engels. My argument takes issue with this way of framing feminist political theory by demonstrating that it rests on a derivation that remains squarely within the logic of malestream political theory. Each of these philosophers made use of a particular discursive trope (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  14
    No More Like Pallas Athena: Displacing Patrilineal Accounts of Modern Feminist Political Theory.Jim Jose - 2004 - Hypatia 19 (4):1-22.
    The history of modern feminist political theories is often framed in terms of the already existing theories of a number of radical nineteenth-century men philosophers such as James Mill, John Stuart Mill, Charles Fourier, Karl Marx, and Friedrich Engels. My argument takes issue with this way of framing feminist political theory by demonstrating that it rests on a derivation that remains squarely within the logic of malestream political theory. Each of these philosophers made use of a particular discursive trope that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. Foucault and Spinoza: philosophies of immanence and the decentred political subject.James Juniper & Jim Jose - 2008 - History of the Human Sciences 21 (2):1-20.
    Deleuze has suggested that Spinoza and Foucault share common concerns, particularly the notion of immanence and their mutual hostility to theories of subjective intentionality and contract-based theories of state power. This article explores these shared concerns. On the one hand Foucault's view of governmentality and its re-theorization of power, sovereignty and resistance provide insights into how humans are constituted as individualized subjects and how populations are formed as subject to specific regimes or mentalities of government. On the other, Spinoza was (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7. Contributors for volume 2.1.Michael Grosso, Mary Hinton, George T. Hole, Anne Lavin, Christopher D. Rodkey, José Barrientos Rostrojo, Steven Segal, Helge Svare, Jim Tuedio & Reinhard Zaiser - 2006 - Philosophical Practice 2 (1).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  9
    Editorial: Anticipatory Systems: Humans Meet Artificial Intelligence.Mu-Yen Chen, Edwin Lughofer, Jose de Jesus Rubio & Yenchun Jim Wu - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. La labor traductora de José Gaos.A. JimÉ, Nez GarcÍ & A. - 2001 - Anales Del Seminario de Historia de la Filosofía 18:219-235.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  87
    Wright on Moore.José L. Zalabardo - 2012 - In Annalisa Coliva (ed.), Mind, meaning, and knowledge: themes from the philosophy of Crispin Wright. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 304–322.
    To the sceptic's contention that I don't know that I have hands because I don't know that there is an external world, the Moorean replies that I know that there is an external world because I know that I have hands. Crispin Wright has argued that the Moorean move is illegitimate, and has tried to block it by limiting the applicability of the principle of the transmission of knowledge by inference—the principle that recognising the validity of an inference from known (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11. Doing Away with Juan Crow: Two Standards for Just Immigration Reform.José Jorge Mendoza - 2015 - APA Newsletter on Hispanic/Latino Issues in Philosophy 15 (2):14-20.
    In 2008 Robert Lovato coined the phrase Juan Crow. Juan Crow is a type of policy or enforcement of immigration laws that discriminate against Latino/as in the United States. This essay looks at the implications this phenomenon has for an ethics of immigration. It argues that Juan Crow, like its predecessor Jim Crow, is not merely a condemnation of federalism, but of any immigration reform that has stricter enforcement as one of its key components. Instead of advocating for increased enforcement, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  35
    Accessibility and transparency of editor conflicts of interest policy instruments in medical journals.Elise Smith, Marie-Josée Potvin & Bryn Williams-Jones - 2012 - Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (11):679-684.
    Background There has been significant discussion about the need to manage conflict of interest (COI) in medical journals. This has lead many journals to implement policies to manage COI for authors and reviewers; however, surprisingly little attention has been focused on the COI of journal editors. Objective The goal of this exploratory study was to determine whether the policies were accessible to the public and to researchers, and to discuss the potential impact on public transparency. Design The authors conducted an (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13. Why there still are no people.Jim Stone - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (1):174-191.
    This paper argues that there are no people. If identity isn't what matters in survival, psychological connectedness isn't what matters either. Further, fissioning cases do not support the claim that connectedness is what matters. I consider Peter Unger's view that what matters is a continuous physical realization of a core psychology. I conclude that if identity isn't what matters in survival, nothing matters. This conclusion is deployed to argue that there are no people. Objections to Eliminativism are considered, especially that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  14.  14
    Wollheim on art’s historicity: an intersection of theoretical art history and the philosophy of art.Jim Berryman - 2023 - British Journal of Aesthetics 64 (2):173-186.
    Art and its Objects by Richard Wollheim had a major impact on aesthetics and the philosophy of art when it was first published in 1968. Of the arguments offered in response to Wollheim’s essay, Jerrold Levinson’s intentional-historical theory of art has been one of the most enduring. Levinson was influenced by three key sections of Wollheim’s enquiry: Section 40, which considers the claim that works of art fall under a concept of art, or that we are disposed to regard certain (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  57
    John Dewey's theory of practical reasoning.Jim Garrison - 1999 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 31 (3):291–312.
  16.  72
    Foucault, Dewey, and Self‐creation.Jim Garrison - 1998 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 30 (2):111–134.
  17.  97
    Philosophy as literature.Jim Marshall - 2008 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 40 (3):383–393.
    How best to introduce philosophical ideas? Is the best and only way by studying the history of philosophy and its rational arguments and discussions? But can literature, usually hived off from philosophy, be used instead and can this be as effective as rational argument? This paper explores these questions. First it considers a text which introduces philosophy through the analysis of literature, in particular James Joyce's 'Araby', arguing that the traditional analytic approach employed by the text, by concentrating on epistemology, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  18.  28
    Slingerland, Edward, Mind and Body in Early China: Beyond Orientalism and the Myth of Holism: Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019, xi + 385 pages.Jim Behuniak - 2019 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 18 (2):305-312.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19.  12
    John Dewey's Theory of Practical Reasoning.Jim Garrison - 1999 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 31 (3):291-312.
  20. Why there are still no people.Jim Stone - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (1):174-192.
    This paper will argue that there are no people. Let me summarize the argument. In part II of what follows, I argue that if identity isn't what matters in survival, psychological connectedness isn't what matters either. Psychological connectedness, according to Derek Parfit, is the 'holding of particular direct psychological connections,' for example, when a belief, a desire, or some other psychological feature continues to be had ; psychological connectedness consists in two other relations—resemblance plus a cause that produces it. For (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  21.  21
    Why There Still Are No People.Jim Stone - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (1):174-192.
    This paper argues that there are no people. If identity isn't what matters in survival, psychological connectedness isn't what matters either. Further, fissioning cases do not support the claim that connectedness is what matters. I consider Peter Unger's view that what matters is a continuous physical realization of a core psychology. I conclude that if identity isn't what matters in survival, nothing matters. This conclusion is deployed to argue that there are no people. Objections to Eliminativism are considered, especially that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  22.  7
    Foucault, Dewey, and Self‐creation.Jim Garrison - 1998 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 30 (2):111-134.
  23.  12
    Philosophy as Literature.Jim Marshall - 2008 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 40 (3):383-393.
    How best to introduce philosophical ideas? Is the best and only way by studying the history of philosophy and its rational arguments and discussions? But can literature, usually hived off from philosophy, be used instead and can this be as effective as rational argument? This paper explores these questions. First it considers a text which introduces philosophy through the analysis of literature, in particular James Joyce's ‘Araby’, arguing that the traditional analytic approach employed by the text, by concentrating on epistemology, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  24.  45
    The embodiment of learning.Jim Horn & Denise Wilburn - 2005 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 37 (5):745–760.
    This paper offers an introduction to the philosophy and science of embodied learning, conceived as both the stabilizing and expansionary process that sustains order and novelty within learners’ worlds enacted through observing and describing. Embodied learning acknowledges stability and change as the purposeful conjoined characteristics that sustain learners. It is, in many respects, a composite theory that represents work from various disciplines. This ‘naturalized epistemology’ conceives a world of fact inevitably imbued with the values that our own structural histories guarantee (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  25.  33
    Street phronesis.Jim Mackenzie - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 25 (2):153–169.
    ABSTRACT Recent discussions of practice in this Journal have appealed to what they describe as the classical concept of practice. In this paper, it is argued that if there is a single classical concept of practice, it has not been described with sufficient clarity for it to be of use in illuminating or correcting anything, even our ‘radically ambiguous’ common-sense understanding of educational practice; and that there are writers today whose understanding of practical wisdom is far superior to that of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  26.  81
    Dewey, Derrida, and 'the double bind'.Jim Garrison - 2003 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 35 (3):349–362.
  27.  35
    Religious upbringing is not as Michael hand describes.Jim Mackenzie - 2004 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 38 (1):129–142.
    Michael Hand, in his recent ‘Religious upbringing reconsidered’ in this journal, has claimed to find a logical problem neglected by earlier writers on religious upbringing and parental rights. In this paper, I argue that he has mis-described the terms in which he poses the alleged problem.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28.  22
    Mathematicians on board: introducing lunar distances to life at sea.Jim Bennett - 2019 - British Journal for the History of Science 52 (1):65-83.
    Nevil Maskelyne, the Cambridge-trained mathematician and later Astronomer Royal, was appointed by the Royal Society to observe the 1761 transit of Venus from the Atlantic island of St Helena, assisted by the mathematical practitioner Robert Waddington. Both had experience of measurement and computation within astronomy and they decided to put their outward and return voyages to a further use by trying out the method of finding longitude at sea by lunar distances. The manuscript and printed records they generated in this (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  20
    Dewey, Derrida, and ‘the Double Bind’.Jim Garrison - 2003 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 35 (3):349-362.
  30.  10
    Street Phronesis.Jim Mackenzie - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 25 (2):153-169.
    Recent discussions of practice in this Journal have appealed to what they describe as the classical concept of practice. In this paper, it is argued that if there is a single classical concept of practice, it has not been described with sufficient clarity for it to be of use in illuminating or correcting anything, even our ‘radically ambiguous’ common-sense understanding of educational practice; and that there are writers today whose understanding of practical wisdom is far superior to that of the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31.  40
    Forms of knowledge and forms of discussion.Jim Mackenzie - 1998 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 30 (1):27–49.
  32.  16
    Religious Upbringing is not as Michael Hand Describes.Jim Mackenzie - 2004 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 38 (1):129-142.
    Michael Hand, in his recent ‘Religious upbringing reconsidered’ in this journal, has claimed to find a logical problem neglected by earlier writers on religious upbringing and parental rights. In this paper, I argue that he has mis-described the terms in which he poses the alleged problem.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  33. Lecciones de filosofía Luis José de la Peña 1827. de la Peña & Luis José - 2005 - Mendoza, Argentina: Universidad Nacional de Cuyo, Facultad de Filosofia y Letras, Instituto de Filosofia Argentina y Americana. Edited by Jalif de Bertranou & Clara Alicia.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  11
    Museums and the History of Science.Jim Bennett - 2005 - Isis 96 (4):602-608.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  35.  6
    The Embodiment of Learning.Denise Wilburn Jim Horn - 2005 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 37 (5):745-760.
    This paper offers an introduction to the philosophy and science of embodied learning, conceived as both the stabilizing and expansionary process that sustains order and novelty within learners’ worlds enacted through observing and describing. Embodied learning acknowledges stability and change as the purposeful conjoined characteristics that sustain learners. It is, in many respects, a composite theory that represents work from various disciplines. This ‘naturalized epistemology’ ( ) conceives a world of fact inevitably imbued with the values that our own structural (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36. Evolution, Consciousness, and the Internality of Mind.Jim Hopkins - 2000 - In P. Carruthers & A. Chamberlen (eds.), Evolution and the Human Mind: Modularity, Language and Meta-Cognition. Cambridge University Press. pp. 276.
    Understanding the notion of innerness that we ascribe to mental items is central to understanding the problem of consciousness, and we can do so in evolutionary and physical terms.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37.  51
    Dangerous Dualisms in Siegel’s Theory of Critical Thinking: A Deweyan Pragmatist Responds.Jim Garrison - 1999 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 33 (2):213–232.
    Harvey Siegel’s conception of critical thinking is riddled with unnecessary and confusing dualisms. He rigidly separates ‘critical skill’ and ‘critical spirit’, the philosophical and the causal, ‘is’ and ‘ought’, and the moral and the epistemological. These dualisms are easily traced to his desire to defend an absolutist and decontextualised epistemology. To the Deweyan naturalist these dualisms are unnecessary. Appealing to the pragmatist notion of beliefs as embodied habits of action evincing emotion, I show how language, meanings and the mind, including (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38.  15
    Dangerous Dualisms in Siegel’s Theory of Critical Thinking: A Deweyan Pragmatist Responds.Jim Garrison - 1999 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 33 (2):213-232.
    Harvey Siegel’s conception of critical thinking is riddled with unnecessary and confusing dualisms. He rigidly separates ‘critical skill’ and ‘critical spirit’, the philosophical and the causal, ‘is’ and ‘ought’, and the moral and the epistemological. These dualisms are easily traced to his desire to defend an absolutist and decontextualised epistemology. To the Deweyan naturalist these dualisms are unnecessary. Appealing to the pragmatist notion of beliefs as embodied habits of action evincing emotion, I show how language, meanings and the mind, including (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39.  13
    Dangerous Dualisms in Siegel’s Theory of Critical Thinking: A Deweyan Pragmatist Responds.Jim Garrison - 1999 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 33 (2):213-232.
    Harvey Siegel’s conception of critical thinking is riddled with unnecessary and confusing dualisms. He rigidly separates ‘critical skill’ and ‘critical spirit’, the philosophical and the causal, ‘is’ and ‘ought’, and the moral and the epistemological. These dualisms are easily traced to his desire to defend an absolutist and decontextualised epistemology. To the Deweyan naturalist these dualisms are unnecessary. Appealing to the pragmatist notion of beliefs as embodied habits of action evincing emotion, I show how language, meanings and the mind, including (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  6
    Forms of Knowledge and Forms of Discussion.Jim Mackenzie - 1998 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 30 (1):27-49.
  41. Una interpretación de la historia universal: en torno a Toynbee, de José Ortega y Gasset.José Mauricio de Carvalho - 2011 - Princípios 18 (30):395-399.
    Resenha de: Normal 0 21 false false false MicrosoftInternetExplorer4 /* Style Definitions */ table.MsoNormalTable {mso-style-name:"Tabela normal"; mso-tstyle-rowband-size:0; mso-tstyle-colband-size:0; mso-style-noshow:yes; mso-style-parent:""; mso-padding-alt:0cm 5.4pt 0cm 5.4pt; mso-para-margin:0cm; mso-para-margin-bottom:.0001pt; mso-pagination:widow-orphan; font-size:10.0pt; font-family:"Times New Roman"; mso-ansi-language:#0400; mso-fareast-language:#0400; mso-bidi-language:#0400;} ORTEGA Y GASSET, José. Una interpretación de la historia universal: en torno a Toynbee . Obras Completas . v. IX. Madrid: Alianza, 1997.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  8
    Too Close to Nature: On the Representational Problems of Death Masks and Life Casts.Jim Berryman - forthcoming - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism.
    While historians of art have found death masks and life casts conceptually problematic, it is also noteworthy that these objects have received scant attention from philosophers of art. In this paper, I begin to redress this omission by offering examples of how the philosophy of art can help us understand these images. Two problems stand out: the problem of representation, for example, what type of representation a death mask is; and the problem of style and historicity, for example, whether images (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  38
    On teaching critical thinking.Jim Mackenzie - 1991 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 23 (1):56–78.
  44. Introduction: Philosophical Essays on Freud.Jim Hopkins - 1982 - In Richard Wollheim & James Hopkins (eds.), Philosophical Essays on Freud. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Psychoanalytic theory can be regarded as a cogent extension of commonsense psychology by interpretive means internal to it.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45. La Prudencia en el Tratado Sobre José de Filón de Alejandría.José María Zamora Calvo - 2003 - Revista Agustiniana 44 (135):623-642.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  17
    Stalky & co.: The adversarial curriculum.Jim Mackenzie - 2002 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 36 (4):609–620.
    A comparison between two teachers drawn from fiction leads to an exploration of the issues between those whose concept of education is focused on the curriculum, and those who understand that pupils are active agents in their education and that therefore some beneficial outcomes can result from pupil subversion of the school. This is developed as a concept of an adversarial curriculum, with particular reference to moral education.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  5
    Stalky & Co.: the Adversarial Curriculum.Jim Mackenzie - 2002 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 36 (4):609-620.
    A comparison between two teachers drawn from fiction leads to an exploration of the issues between those whose concept of education is focused on the curriculum, and those who understand that pupils are active agents in their education and that therefore some beneficial outcomes can result from pupil subversion of the school. This is developed as a concept of an adversarial curriculum, with particular reference to moral education.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  18
    Still irrelevant to us.Jim Mackenzie - 2004 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 38 (4):639–662.
    Michael Hand presents the problem for his paper succinctly in his response: ‘religious beliefs, since they are not known to be true, cannot be imparted by the p.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  92
    Why can’t what is true be valuable?Jim Hutchinson - 2019 - Synthese (7):1-20.
    In recent discussions of the so-called “value of truth,” it is assumed that what is valuable in the relevant way is not the things that are true, but only various states and activities associated with those things: knowing them, investigating them, etc. I consider all the arguments I know of for this assumption, and argue that none provide good reason to accept it. By examining these arguments, we gain a better appreciation of what the value of the things that are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  40
    Bādarāyana: Creator of Systematic Theology: JOSÉ PEREIRA.JosÉ Pereira - 1986 - Religious Studies 22 (2):193-204.
    It is sometimes asserted that Philo of Alexandria is the creator of systematic theology – not because he created systematics , that is, a body of doctrine classified and integrated by a set of principles defined in philosophical terms, but because he created theology , that is, a mode of philosophizing which derives its main categories from a supernatural revelation. Such a mode was pursued by Philo's Christian disciples, among whom was Origen , one of the first of his faith (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 982