Results for ' Danto holding a Cartesian view, of the history of philosophy'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  3
    Danto as Systematic Philosopher, or Comme on Lit Danto En Français.David Carrier - 1993 - In Mark Rollins (ed.), Danto and His Critics. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 13–29.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  94
    The transfiguration of the commonplace: a philosophy of art.Arthur Coleman Danto - 1981 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Mr. Danto argues that recent developments in the artworld, in particular the production of works of art that cannot be told from ordinary things, make urgent the need for a new theory of art and make plain the factors such a theory can and cannot involve. In the course of constructing such a theory, he seeks to demonstrate the relationship between philosophy and art, as well as the connections that hold between art and social institutions and art (...). The book distinguishes what belongs to artistic theory from what has traditionally been confused with it, namely aesthetic theory and offers as well a systematic account of metaphor, expression, and style, together with an original account 0f artistic representation. A wealth of examples, drawn especially from recent and contemporary art, illuminate the argument. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  3.  14
    Absence of Embodied Subject in the History of Philosophy.Dr Elham Shirvani & Masoud Shirvani - 2023 - Open Journal of Philosophy 13 (3):478-494.
    There have been several important breakthroughs in the fields of philosophy of mind, philosophy of religion, and neuroscience in recent centuries. Despite their complexities and varying opinions in each field, the majority of these breakthroughs tend to view human consciousness as a concrete reality influenced by physiological, social, and environmental factors. This raises the question of why such a dominant perspective did not prevail throughout the history of philosophy and why there were inclinations to deny it. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  57
    Descartes, consciousness and depersonalization: Viewing the history of philosophy from a Strausian perspective.Avner Cohen - 1984 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 9 (1):7-28.
    This paper develops particular Strausian-like themes on the formation and structure of the Cartesian problematic. Particularly, my interest is to link the Cartesian ‘invention’ of consciousness (or ‘the mental’) in the philosophy of mind with the issues of representation and ‘the problem of the external world’ in epistemology. The Cartesian novelty becomes clear by comparing Cartesian scepticism with Greek classical scepticism. I end with some speculative clinical (i.e., psychiatric) suggestions on possible roots of the (...) invention. Keywords: Consciousness, Externalization, Dualism, Self-World CiteULike Connotea Del.icio.us What's this? (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Philosophy's Past: Cognitive Values and the History of Philosophy.Phil Corkum - 2023 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 108 (3):585-606.
    Recent authors hold that the role of historical scholarship within contemporary philosophical practice is to question current assumptions, to expose vestiges or to calibrate intuitions. On these views, historical scholarship is dispensable, since these roles can be achieved by nonhistorical methods. And the value of historical scholarship is contingent, since the need for the role depends on the presence of questionable assumptions, vestiges or comparable intuitions. In this paper I draw an analogy between scientific and philosophical practice, in order to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  32
    Lorenzo Valla and the Traditions and Transmissions of Philosophy.Christopher S. Celenza - 2005 - Journal of the History of Ideas 66 (4):483-506.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Ideas 66.4 (2005) 483-506 [Access article in PDF] Lorenzo Valla and the Traditions and Transmissions of Philosophy C. S. Celenza Johns Hopkins University What is "philosophy"? Who is a "philosopher"? These questions underlay much of Salvatore Camporeale's work, and they are deeper than one might suppose. We can begin with one of Camporeale's favorite figures, Lorenzo Valla, and listen to one (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  9
    Lorenzo Valla and the Traditions and Transmissions of Philosophy.Christopher S. Celenza - 2005 - Journal of the History of Ideas 66 (4):483-506.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Ideas 66.4 (2005) 483-506 [Access article in PDF] Lorenzo Valla and the Traditions and Transmissions of Philosophy C. S. Celenza Johns Hopkins University What is "philosophy"? Who is a "philosopher"? These questions underlay much of Salvatore Camporeale's work, and they are deeper than one might suppose. We can begin with one of Camporeale's favorite figures, Lorenzo Valla, and listen to one (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  4
    Lorenzo Valla and the Traditions and Transmissions of Philosophy.S. Celenza - 2005 - Journal of the History of Ideas 66 (4):483-506.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Ideas 66.4 (2005) 483-506 [Access article in PDF] Lorenzo Valla and the Traditions and Transmissions of Philosophy C. S. Celenza Johns Hopkins University What is "philosophy"? Who is a "philosopher"? These questions underlay much of Salvatore Camporeale's work, and they are deeper than one might suppose. We can begin with one of Camporeale's favorite figures, Lorenzo Valla, and listen to one (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  61
    The history of Ideas as philosophy and history.Michael Rosen - 2011 - History of Political Thought 32 (4):691-720.
    This article argues for a conception of the history of ideas that treats philosophy historically while avoiding sociological reductionism. On the view presented here, philosophical problems characteristically arise from a conflict of commitments, at least some of which have roots in wider forms of life and ways of seeing the world. In bringing such 'doxa' to our attention, the history of ideas, it is argued, plays a role that is both genuinely historical and, at the same time, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10.  23
    Beyond the edge of certainty: Essays in contemporary science and philosophy.Darrel E. Christensen - 1967 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 5 (4):388-389.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:388 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY Beyond the Edge of Certainty: Essays in Contemporary Science and Philosophy. Edited with an Introduction by Robert G. Colodny. (Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1965.) This is the second volume of lectures on various current topics in the philosophy of the physical, biological, and social sciences which has been published under the auspices of the Center for Philosophy of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Pyrrhonian skepticism.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.) - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Throughout the history of philosophy, skepticism has posed one of the central challenges of epistemology. Opponents of skepticism--including externalists, contextualists, foundationalists, and coherentists--have focussed largely on one particular variety of skepticism, often called Cartesian or Academic skepticism, which makes the radical claim that nobody can know anything. However, this version of skepticism is something of a straw man, since virtually no philosopher endorses this radical skeptical claim. The only skeptical view that has been truly held--by Sextus, Montaigne, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  12.  43
    Comparisons in the history of philosophy: a review of The metaphysics of Margaret Cavendish and Anne Conway: monism, vitalism, and self-motion, by Marcy P. Lascano, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2023, pp. 240, £54.00 (hb), ISBN: 9780197651636. [REVIEW]Peter West - 2023 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (3).
    In The Metaphysics of Margaret Cavendish and Anne Conway, Marcy P. Lascano holds up the metaphysical views of two early modern women philosophers alongside one another in order to demonstrate that...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  5
    The history of physics: a biographical approach.Howard T. Milhorn - 2008 - College Station, TX: Virtualbookworm.com.
    The history of physics ranges from antiquity to modern string theory. Since early times, human beings have sought to understand the workings of nature--why unsupported objects drop to the ground, why different materials have different properties, and so forth. The emergence of physics as a science, distinct from natural philosophy, began with the scientific revolution of the 16th and 17th centuries when the scientific method came into vogue. Speculation was no longer acceptable; research was required. The beginning of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  22
    A Contextualist History of Cartesian Philosophy: Roger Ariew’s Descartes and the First Cartesians.Domenico Collacciani - 2018 - Perspectives on Science 26 (5):521-532.
    The title Descartes and the First Cartesians only partly reflects the scope of the research presented in Roger Ariew's latest book. To be sure, this study does offer a new and extensive account of the work of the first Cartesians and thus a new perspective on the historical phenomenon that was seventeenth century Cartesianism. Yet it does so on the basis of a vast survey of the Scholastic context from which the new philosophy emerged. The investigation of Cartesianism is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  44
    Empirical vs. Rational Order in the History of Philosophy.Clark Butler - 1994 - The Owl of Minerva 26 (1):29-34.
    A problem is posed by differences between the temporal order of philosophers in the history of philosophy and the rational order in which “definitions of the absolute” upheld by these philosophers appear in Hegel’s Logic. Hegel holds, according to § 88 of the Encyclopedia, both that the Logic reconstructs the history of philosophy on the level of pure thought and that chronological history deviates in places from the rational sequence. A problem is posed for anyone (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  56
    Mathematics and Necessity: Essays in the History of Philosophy (review).Daniel Sutherland - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (3):426-427.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 41.3 (2003) 426-427 [Access article in PDF] Timothy Smiley, editor. Mathematics and Necessity: Essays in the History of Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000. Pp. ix + 166. Cloth, $35.00.Mathematics and Necessity contains essays by M. F. Burnyeat, Ian Hacking, and Jonathan Bennett based on lectures given to the British Academy in 1998. All concern the history (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  22
    Arthur Danto, the End of Art, and the Philosophical View of History.Chiel van den Akker - 2019 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 13 (2):235-256.
    This essay takes Arthur Danto’s end-of-art thesis as a case in point of a substantive philosophy of history. Such philosophy explains the direction that art has taken and why that direction could not have been different. Danto never scrutinized the philosophy of history that his end-of-art thesis presumes. I aim to do that by drawing a distinction between what I refer to as the common view of history and the philosophical view of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  61
    Cartesian Reflections: Essays on Descartes's Philosophy.Deborah J. Brown - 2010 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88 (4):731-734.
    HOME . ABOUT US . CONTACT US HELP . PUBLISH WITH US . LIBRARIANS Search in or Explore Browse Publications A-Z Browse Subjects A-Z Advanced Search University of Cambridge SIGN IN Register | Why Register? | Sign Out | Got a Voucher? prev abstract next Two Approaches to Reading the Historical Descartes A Devout Catholic? Knowledge of The Mental Thought and Language Descartes as A Natural Philosopher Substance Dualism Notes Two Approaches to Reading the Historical Descartes Author: Desmond M. Clarke (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  3
    Beyond the Edge of Certainty: Essays in Contemporary Science and Philosophy (review). [REVIEW]Darrel E. Christensen - 1967 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 5 (4):388-389.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:388 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY Beyond the Edge of Certainty: Essays in Contemporary Science and Philosophy. Edited with an Introduction by Robert G. Colodny. (Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1965.) This is the second volume of lectures on various current topics in the philosophy of the physical, biological, and social sciences which has been published under the auspices of the Center for Philosophy of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  21
    The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy (review).Frederick Rauscher - 1998 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 36 (4):627-628.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy by J. B. SchneewindFrederick RauscherJ. B. Schneewind. The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. Pp. xxii + 624. Cloth $69.95.For most of the twentieth century ethics has been relegated to the status of a hanger-on to other pursuits in philosophy. Only in the past three (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  90
    Introduction: Danto and his critics: After the end of art and art history.David Carrier - 1998 - History and Theory 37 (4):1–16.
    In Bielefeld, Germany in April, 1997 an author conference was devoted to Arthur C. Danto's 1995 Mellon Lectures After the End of Art: Contemporary Art and the Pale of History . This essay provides an introduction to seven essays given at that conference and expanded for this Theme Issue of History and Theory. Danto presented his view of the nature of art in The Transfiguration of the Commonplace . He then added in the Mellon lectures a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22. The Philosophy of Inquiry and Global Problems: The Intellectual Revolution Needed to Create a Better World.Nicholas Maxwell - 2024 - London: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Bad philosophy is responsible for the climate and nature crises, and other global problems too that threaten our future. That sounds mad, but it is true. A philosophy of science, or of theatre or life is a view about what are, or ought to be, the aims and methods of science, theatre or life. It is in this entirely legitimate sense of “philosophy” that bad philosophy is responsible for the crises we face. First, and in a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  52
    Carnap, Kuhn, and the History of Science: A Reply to Thomas Uebel.J. C. Pinto de Oliveira - 2015 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 46 (1):215-223.
    The purpose of this article is to respond to Thomas Uebel’s criticisms of my comments regarding the current revisionism of Carnap’s work and its relations to Kuhn. I begin by pointing out some misunderstandings in the interpretation of my article. I then discuss some aspects related to Carnap’s view of the history of science. First, I emphasize that it was not due to a supposed affinity between Kuhn’s conceptions and those of logical positivists that Kuhn was invited to write (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24. Handbook of the history of logic.Dov M. Gabbay, John Woods & Akihiro Kanamori (eds.) - 2004 - Boston: Elsevier.
    Greek, Indian and Arabic Logic marks the initial appearance of the multi-volume Handbook of the History of Logic. Additional volumes will be published when ready, rather than in strict chronological order. Soon to appear are The Rise of Modern Logic: From Leibniz to Frege. Also in preparation are Logic From Russell to Gödel, The Emergence of Classical Logic, Logic and the Modalities in the Twentieth Century, and The Many-Valued and Non-Monotonic Turn in Logic. Further volumes will follow, including Mediaeval (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  24
    Introduction: Danto and His Critics: Art History, Historiography and After the End of Art.David Carrier - 1998 - History and Theory 37 (4):1-16.
    In Bielefeld, Germany in April, 1997 an author conference was devoted to Arthur C. Danto's 1995 Mellon Lectures After the End of Art: Contemporary Art and the Pale of History. This essay provides an introduction to seven essays given at that conference and expanded for this Theme Issue of History and Theory. Danto presented his view of the nature of art in The Transfiguration of the Commonplace. He then added in the Mellon lectures a sociological perspective (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26. Imagination, eliminativism, and the pre-history of consciousness.Thomas Nigel - 1998 - Consciousness Research Abstracts 3.
    Classical and medieval writers had no term for consciousness in anything like the modern sense, and their philosophy seems not to have been troubled by the mind-body problem. Contemporary eliminativists find strong support in this fact for their claim that consciousness does not exist, or, at least, is not an appropriate scientific explanandum. They typically hold that contemporary conceptions of consciousness are artefacts of Descartes' (now outmoded) views about matter and his unrealistic craving for epistemological certainty. Essentially, they say, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  22
    The Side View: Hadot and Sloterdijk on the Practice of Philosophy.Adam Robbert - 2017 - Cosmos and History 13 (1):1-14.
    Normal 0 false false false EN-US JA X-NONE This essay describes Peter Sloterdijk’s “side view” of philosophy. That is, it describes the self-disciplines that make philosophical activity possible. Along similar lines, the paper draws on the work of Pierre Hadot, who also reads philosophy as an askēsis or exercise of self-transformation. Bringing together the work of Sloterdijk and Hadot, the essay reframes the question, What is Philosophy? by asking, Who is the philosopher? To this end, the essays (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  43
    The Polymorphism of Human Consciousness and the Prospects for a Lonerganian History of Philosophy.Mark D. Morelli - 1995 - International Philosophical Quarterly 35 (4):379-402.
    Lonergan's account of human consciousness as polymorphic self-presence differs significantly from both the variety of contemporary reductionistic accounts and phenomenological treatments still influenced strongly by Cartesian suppositions and/or Kantian restrictions. It is argued that Lonergan's account grounds not only a critical meta-philosophy, but also provides a heuristic structure for a nuanced genetic account of philosophic differences. In this regard, Lonergan's account is claimed to be an adequate grounding for a thorough contemporary response to the Hegelian requirement that philosophers (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. The Riddle of Hume's Treatise: Skepticism, Naturalism, and Irreligion.Paul Russell - 2008 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY PRIZE for the best published book in the history of philosophy [Awarded in 2010] _______________ -/- Although it is widely recognized that David Hume's A Treatise of Human Nature (1739-40) belongs among the greatest works of philosophy, there is little agreement about the correct way to interpret his fundamental intentions. It is an established orthodoxy among almost all commentators that skepticism and naturalism are the two dominant themes in this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  30. Imagination, eliminativism, and the pre-history of consciousness.Nigel J. T. Thomas - 1998 - Consciousness Research Abstracts 3.
    Classical and medieval writers had no term for consciousness in anything like the modern sense, and their philosophy seems not to have been troubled by the mind-body problem. Contemporary eliminativists find strong support in this fact for their claim that consciousness does not exist, or, at least, is not an appropriate scientific explanandum. They typically hold that contemporary conceptions of consciousness are artefacts of Descartes' (now outmoded) views about matter and his unrealistic craving for epistemological certainty. Essentially, they say, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Whatever Should We Do with Cartesian Method?—Reclaiming Descartes for the History of Science.John A. Schuster - 1993 - In Stephen Voss (ed.), Essays on the philosophy and science of René Descartes. New York: Oxford University Press.
    This chapter describes the discovery, perfection, and application of the scientific method as the Scientific Revolution happens. Bacon, Galileo, Harvey, Huygens, and Newton were singularly successful in persuading posterity that they contributed to the invention of a single, transferable, and efficacious scientific method. The treatment of Descartes' method by historians of science and historians of philosophy has been no exception to this pattern. The Discours de la methode has been seen as one of the most important methodological treatises in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. The end of art: A philosophical defense.Arthur C. Danto - 1998 - History and Theory 37 (4):127–143.
    This essay constructs philosophical defenses against criticisms of my theory of the end of art. These have to do with the definition of art; the concept of artistic quality; the role of aesthetics; the relationship between philosophy and art; how to answer the question "But is it art?"; the difference between the end of art and "the death of painting"; historical imagination and the future; the method of using indiscernible counterparts, like Warhol's Brillo Box and the Brillo cartons it (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  33.  43
    Danto, history, and the tragedy of human existence.F. R. Ankersmit - 2003 - History and Theory 42 (3):291–304.
    Philosophy of history is the Cinderella of contemporary philosophy. Philosophers rarely believe that the issues dealt with by philosophers of history are matters of any great theoretical interest or urgency. In their view philosophy of history rarely goes beyond the question of how results that have already been achieved elsewhere can or should be applied to the domain of historical writing. Moreover, contemporary philosophers of history have done desperately little to dispel the low (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34.  68
    The End of Art: A Philosophical Defense.Arthur C. Danto - 1998 - History and Theory 37 (4):127-143.
    This essay constructs philosophical defenses against criticisms of my theory of the end of art. These have to do with the definition of art; the concept of artistic quality; the role of aesthetics; the relationship between philosophy and art; how to answer the question “But is it art?”; the difference between the end of art and “the death of painting”; historical imagination and the future; the method of using indiscernible counterparts, like Warhol's Brillo Box and the Brillo cartons it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  35. Technology, Philosophy, and the Mastery of Nature: Leibniz' Critique of Cartesian Mechanics.Joseph Kevin Cosgrove - 1996 - Dissertation, The Catholic University of America
    The goal of the modern scientific project, as defined by such thinkers as Descartes and Bacon, is "mastery of nature." Martin Heidegger, in an interpretation of mastery of nature that has left its imprint on post-modern critique of science, maintains that the essence of modern science lies in a projection of "technological being" upon nature. This projective "assault" has its origin in the "self-grounding" project of modern metaphysics, in which the human subject attempts to secure a self-sufficient position over against (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  48
    Cartesian Privations: How Pierre-Sylvain Regis Used Material Causation to Provide a Cartesian Account of Sin.Joseph Anderson - 2016 - Journal of Early Modern Studies 5 (2):81-100.
    Descartes’s very brief explanations of human responsibility for sin and divine innocence of sin include references to the idea that evil is a privation rather than a real thing. It is not obvious, though, that privation fits naturally in Descartes’s reductionistic metaphysics, nor is it clear precisely what role his privation doctrine plays in his theodicy. These issues are made clear by contrasting Descartes’s use of privations with that of Suarez, particularly in light of reoccurring objections to privation theory. These (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  30
    Cartesian Views: Papers Presented to Richard A. Watson[REVIEW]Patricia A. Easton - 2008 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (2):320-321.
    Cartesian Views is a fitting tribute to a man of many parts, to use Alison Wylie’s apt description . Richard A. Watson has provoked, evoked, and invoked new directions in Cartesian scholarship—both methodologically and substantively. Watson’s Downfall of Cartesianism and its sequel, The Breakdown of Metaphysics , have become required reading for students of early modern philosophy and are largely responsible for the revival of many “minor” Cartesians, while serving as sourcebook for methodological attention to history (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  47
    Cartesian views: Papers presented to Richard A. Watson.Patricia A. Easton - 2008 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (2):pp. 320-321.
    Cartesian Views is a fitting tribute to a man of many parts, to use Alison Wylie’s apt description . Richard A. Watson has provoked, evoked, and invoked new directions in Cartesian scholarship—both methodologically and substantively. Watson’s Downfall of Cartesianism and its sequel, The Breakdown of Metaphysics , have become required reading for students of early modern philosophy and are largely responsible for the revival of many “minor” Cartesians, while serving as sourcebook for methodological attention to history (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  4
    Schoeman’s Alternative to the Liberal View of the Family.Richard O’Neil - 1987 - Philosophy Research Archives 13:217-224.
    Ferdinand Schoeman criticizes the liberal view of the family which holds that parental rights are based in and limited by parental duties to the child. Instead he proposes the construction of principles based on the value of familial intimacy. Schoeman claims that only by recognizing the value of intimacy can we account for the degree of autonomy we legitimately grant parents in their relations with their children. In opposition, I argue that he misinterprets the liberal view. A correct interpretation allows (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. The history of philosophy in contemporary philosophy: The view from germany.Lorenz B. Puntel - 1991 - Topoi 10 (2):147-153.
    I have frequently mentioned objective problems and topics in the preceding sections. But what exactly is the force of ‘objective’ here? As my remarks should have made clear I have been using ‘objective’ to contrast with ‘purely historical’. A ‘purely historical’ approach never gets beyond reproduction, commentary, and interpretation. I call an approach ‘objective’ when it involves a philosopher who advances his own theses and claims. This minimal understanding of ‘objectivity’ (in the context of my remarks in this paper) by (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  41. The history of philosophy and the philosophy of history in developmental psychology: A view of the issues.Richard M. Lerner - 1983 - In Developmental psychology: historical and philosophical perspectives. Hillsdale, N.J.: L. Erlbaum Associates.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  14
    The restless clock: a history of the centuries-long argument over what makes living things tick.Jessica Riskin - 2016 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    A core principle of modern science holds that a scientific explanation must not attribute will or agency to natural phenomena.The Restless Clock examines the origins and history of this, in particular as it applies to the science of living things. This is also the story of a tradition of radicals—dissenters who embraced the opposite view, that agency is an essential and ineradicable part of nature. Beginning with the church and courtly automata of early modern Europe, Jessica Riskin guides us (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  43. Descartes’ Proof of the Essence of Matter and the Cartesian Scientific System.Athanasse Raftopoulos - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Research 21:209-229.
    It has been a traditional claim that Descartes sought to construct a deductive scientific system in which everything could be deduced from a priori truths. I shall call this thesis strong a priorism. In view of the overwhelming amount of evidence that Descartes thought experience to be a necessary part of his method, the traditional interpretation has undergone several transformations. One interpretation resulting from this transformation holds that Descartes sought to prove the first principles of natural philosophy in an (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  12
    Descartes’ Proof of the Essence of Matter and the Cartesian Scientific System.Athanasse Raftopoulos - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Research 21:209-229.
    It has been a traditional claim that Descartes sought to construct a deductive scientific system in which everything could be deduced from a priori truths. I shall call this thesis strong a priorism. In view of the overwhelming amount of evidence that Descartes thought experience to be a necessary part of his method, the traditional interpretation has undergone several transformations. One interpretation resulting from this transformation holds that Descartes sought to prove the first principles of natural philosophy in an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  42
    Effective history and the end of art: From Nietzsche to Danto.Ingrid Scheibler - 1999 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 25 (6):1-28.
    This article takes its shape from a recent conference at the School of Visual Arts in NYC on the theme, 'Tradition and the New: Educating the Artist for the Millennium'. Central to the way the conference was advertised and described was an implicit tendency to view tradition as wholly separate from the new. While the conference did not itself make a theoretical argument for the opposition of tradition and the new, Arthur Danto's recent elaboration of a thesis of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. The Hermeneutical Status of the History of Science: the Views of Hélène Metzger. A Comment in Science in Reflection: The Israel Colloquium: Studies in History, Philosophy, and Sociology of Science (Volume 3).P. Kerszberg - 1988 - Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 110:145-150.
  47.  56
    The Exemplification Theory of History: Narrativist Philosophy and the Autonomy of History.Chiel van den Akker - 2012 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 6 (2):236-257.
    The “exemplification theory of history” is proposed to account for the relationship between the past and historical narratives. The theory states that what belongs to the past according to some narrative does so in order to exemplify the historical thesis of that narrative. As such the theory explains how the past receives its meaning. This implies that the past has no intrinsic historical meaning itself. Moreover, it follows that historical narratives possess an autonomy of their own with regard to (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  41
    Schoeman’s Alternative to the Liberal View of the Family.Richard O’Neil - 1987 - Philosophy Research Archives 13:217-224.
    Ferdinand Schoeman criticizes the liberal view of the family which holds that parental rights are based in and limited by parental duties to the child. Instead he proposes the construction of principles based on the value of familial intimacy. Schoeman claims that only by recognizing the value of intimacy can we account for the degree of autonomy we legitimately grant parents in their relations with their children. In opposition, I argue that he misinterprets the liberal view. A correct interpretation allows (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. The Category of the person: anthropology, philosophy, history.Michael Carrithers, Steven Collins & Steven Lukes (eds.) - 1985 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    The concept that peope have of themselves as a 'person' is one of the most intimate notions that they hold. Yet the way in which the category of the person is conceived varies over time and space. In this volume, anthropologists, philosophers, and historians examine the notion of the person in different cultures, past and present. Taking as their starting point a lecture on the person as a category of the human mind, given by Marcel Mauss in 1938, the contributors (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  50. Arthur Danto’s Andy Warhol: the Embodiment of Theory in Art and the Pragmatic Turn.Stephen Snyder - forthcoming - Leitmotiv:135-151.
    Arthur Danto’s recent book, Andy Warhol, leads the reader through the story of the iconic American’s artistic life highlighted by a philosophical commentary, a commentary that merges Danto’s aesthetic theory with the artist himself. Inspired by Warhol’s Brillo Box installation, art that in Danto’s eyes was indiscernible from the everyday boxes it represented, Danto developed a theory that is able to differentiate art from non-art by employing the body of conceptual art theory manifest in what he (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 1000