Results for 'Joseph McCahery'

985 found
Order:
  1.  12
    Incomplete Contracts Theories of the Firm and Comparative Corporate Governance.Joseph A. McCahery & William W. Bratton - 2001 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 2 (2).
    This article draws on key models of monitoring and blockholding articulated in the incomplete contracts theory of the firm. Under incomplete contracts theory, different governance systems have incentive structures that entail different tradeoffs—tradeoffs between ownership concentration and liquidity, between monitoring and management initiative, and between private rent-seeking and activity benefiting shareholders as a group. The tradeoffs delimit opportunities for productive cross-reference. More specifically, blockholder systems, such as those in Europe, subsidize monitoring by permitting blockholders to reap private benefits of control (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  45
    Solidarity: The Analysis of a Social Movement: Poland 1980–1.Michael Bernhard & Joseph McCahery - 1984 - Telos: Critical Theory of the Contemporary 1984 (62):231-240.
    Solidarity is a complex theoretical and historical investigation of one of the most dynamic social movements in post-World War II Europe. For some time now, Touraine has attempted to develop a comprehensive theory of social movements. In Solidarity, he and fellow researchers François Dubet, Michel Wieviorka, and Jan Strezelecki, apply the theories of action, movement and sociological intervention elaborated in The Voice and The Eye to the situation in Poland 1980-1. Solidarity is one of many attempts by Touraine to combine (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Causes and explanations: A structural-model approach. Part I: Causes.Joseph Y. Halpern & Judea Pearl - 2005 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56 (4):843-887.
    We propose a new definition of actual causes, using structural equations to model counterfactuals. We show that the definition yields a plausible and elegant account of causation that handles well examples which have caused problems for other definitions and resolves major difficulties in the traditional account.
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   168 citations  
  4. Weaseling away the indispensability argument.Joseph Melia - 2000 - Mind 109 (435):455-480.
    According to the indispensability argument, the fact that we quantify over numbers, sets and functions in our best scientific theories gives us reason for believing that such objects exist. I examine a strategy to dispense with such quantification by simply replacing any given platonistic theory by the set of sentences in the nominalist vocabulary it logically entails. I argue that, as a strategy, this response fails: for there is no guarantee that the nominalist world that go beyond the set of (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   175 citations  
  5. Facing diversity: The case of epistemic abstinence.Joseph Raz - 1990 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (1):3-46.
  6.  41
    Degrees of unsolvability.Joseph Robert Shoenfield - 1972 - New York,: American Elsevier.
  7. Authority and justification.Joseph Raz - 1985 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1):3-29.
  8.  95
    Looks and the immediacy of visual objectual knowledge.Joseph Shieber - 2017 - Analysis 77 (4):741-750.
    In his recent paper ‘Knowing What Things Look Like’, Matthew McGrath offers a challenge to the idea that knowing an object by seeing it, ‘visual objectual knowledge’ is an instance of immediate knowledge. I offer supporters of the notion of immediate visual objectual knowledge two potential strategies for blocking McGrath’s argument: either by questioning McGrath’s claim about the role that knowing what an object looks like plays in visual objectual knowledge or by denying that any explanation of how knowing what (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  9. Ramseyfication and theoretical content.Joseph Melia & Juha Saatsi - 2006 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57 (3):561-585.
    Model theoretic considerations purportedly show that a certain version of structural realism, one which articulates the nvtion of structure via Ramsey sentences, is in fact trivially true. In this paper we argue that the structural realist is by no means forced to Ramseyfy in the manner assumed in the formal proof. However, the structural realist's reprise is short-lived. For, as we show, there are related versions of the model theoretic argument which cannot be so easily blocked by the structural realist. (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  10. An empirical investigation of the influence of selected personal, organizational and moral intensity factors on ethical decision making.Joseph G. P. Paolillo & Scott J. Vitell - 2002 - Journal of Business Ethics 35 (1):65 - 74.
    This exploratory study of ethical decision making by individuals in organizations found moral intensity, as defined by Jones (1991), to significantly influence ethical decision making intentions of managers. Moral intensity explained 37% and 53% of the variance in ethical decision making in two decision-making scenarios. In part, the results of this research support our theoretical understanding of ethical/unethical decision-making and serve as a foundation for future research.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  11.  93
    A partial defense of intuition on naturalist grounds.Joseph Shieber - 2012 - Synthese 187 (2):321-341.
    The debate concerning the role of intuitions in philosophy has been characterized by a fundamental disagreement between two main camps. The first, the autonomists, hold that, due to the use in philosophical investigation of appeals to intuition, most of the central questions of philosophy can in principle be answered by philosophical investigation and argument without relying on the sciences. The second, the naturalists, deny the possibility of a priori knowledge and are skeptical of the role of intuition in providing evidence (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  12.  86
    Methodological individualism.Joseph Heath - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    (1968 [1922]). It amounts to the claim that social phenomena must be explained by showing how they result from individual actions, which in turn must be explained through reference to the intentional states that motivate the individual actors. It involves, in other words, a commitment to the primacy of what Talcott Parsons would later call “the action frame of reference” (Parsons 1937: 43-51) in social-scientific explanation. It is also sometimes described as the claim that explanations of “macro” social phenomena must (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  13. The many sciences and the one world.Geoffrey Joseph - 1980 - Journal of Philosophy 77 (12):773-791.
  14. Holes, haecceitism and two conceptions of determinism.Joseph Melia - 1999 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50 (4):639--64.
    In this paper I claim that Earman and Norton 's hole argument against substantivalist interpretations of General Relativity assumes that the substantivalist must adopt a conception of determinism which I argue is unsatisfactory. Butterfield and others have responded to the hole argument by finding a conception of determinism open to the substantivalist that is not prone to the hole argument. But, unfortunately for the substantivalist, I argue this conception also turns out to be unsatisfactory. Accordingly, I search for a conception (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  15. Live-in domestics, seasonal workers, and others hard to locate on the map of democracy.Joseph H. Carens - 2008 - Journal of Political Philosophy 16 (4):419-445.
  16. Natural goodness and natural evil.Joseph Millum - 2006 - Ratio 19 (2):199–213.
    In Natural Goodness Philippa Foot gives an analysis of the concepts we use to describe the characteristics of living things. She suggests that we describe them in functional terms, and this allows us to judge organisms as good or defective depending on how well they perform their distinctive functions. Foot claims that we can judge intentional human actions in the same way: the virtues contribute in obvious ways to good human functioning, and this provides us with grounds for making moral (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  17.  74
    The ability of internal auditors to identify ethical dilemmas.Joseph M. Larkin - 2000 - Journal of Business Ethics 23 (4):401 - 409.
    This study surveys the internal audit department of a large financial services organization. Respondents were challenged to recognize and evaluate ethical and unethical situations often encountered in practice. Four key demographic variables were investigated: gender, age, years of employment and peer group influence. For the most part, respondents view themselves as more ethical than their peers. There does appear to be a gender effect suggesting females' ability to identify ethical behavior better than their male counterparts. This study contributes to the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  18.  82
    Randomness and computability: Open questions.Joseph S. Miller & André Nies - 2006 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 12 (3):390-410.
    It is time for a new paper about open questions in the currently very active area of randomness and computability. Ambos-Spies and Kučera presented such a paper in 1999 [1]. All the question in it have been solved, except for one: is KL-randomness different from Martin-Löf randomness? This question is discussed in Section 6.Not all the questions are necessarily hard—some simply have not been tried seriously. When we think a question is a major one, and therefore likely to be hard, (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  19.  66
    The challenge of leadership accountability for integrity capacity as a strategic asset.Joseph A. Petrick & John F. Quinn - 2001 - Journal of Business Ethics 34 (3-4):331 - 343.
    The authors identify the challenge of holding contemporary business leaders accountable for enhancing the intangible strategic asset of integrity capacity in organizations. After defining integrity capacity and framing it as part of a strategic resource model of sustainable global competitive advantage, the stakeholder costs of integrity capacity neglect are delineated. To address this neglect issue, the authors focus on the cultivation of judgment integrity to handle behavioral, moral and hypothesized economic complexities as key dimensions of integrity capacity. Finally, the authors (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  20. Essential membership.Joseph LaPorte - 1997 - Philosophy of Science 64 (1):96-112.
    In this paper I take issue with the doctrine that organisms belong of their very essence to the natural kinds (or biological taxa, if these are not kinds) to which they belong. This view holds that any human essentially belongs to the species Homo sapiens, any feline essentially belongs to the cat family, and so on. I survey the various competing views in biological systematics. These offer different explanations for what it is that makes a member of one species, family, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  21. Against modalism.Joseph Melia - 1992 - Philosophical Studies 68 (1):35 - 56.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  22.  70
    Rigid designators.Joseph LaPorte - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  23. Propositions, numbers, and the problem of arbitrary identification.Joseph G. Moore - 1999 - Synthese 120 (2):229-263.
    Those inclined to believe in the existence of propositions as traditionally conceived might seek to reduce them to some other type of entity. However, parsimonious propositionalists of this type are confronted with a choice of competing candidates – for example, sets of possible worlds, and various neo-Russellian and neo-Fregean constructions. It is argued that this choice is an arbitrary one, and that it closely resembles the type of problematic choice that, as Benacerraf pointed out, bedevils the attempt to reduce numbers (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  24.  83
    Constitutive rules and speech-act analysis.Joseph Ransdell - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (13):385-400.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  25. The politics of postmodern philosophy of science.Joseph Rouse - 1991 - Philosophy of Science 58 (4):607-627.
    Modernism in the philosophy of science demands a unified story about what makes an inquiry scientific (or a successful science). Fine's "natural ontological attitude" (NOA) is "postmodern" in joining trust in local scientific practice with suspicion toward any global interpretation of science to legitimate or undercut that trust. I consider four readings of this combination of trust and suspicion and their consequences for the autonomy and cultural credibility of the sciences. Three readings take respectively Fine's trusting attitude, his emphasis upon (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  26. A relative consistency proof.Joseph R. Shoenfield - 1954 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 19 (1):21-28.
    LetCbe an axiom system formalized within the first order functional calculus, and letC′ be related toCas the Bernays-Gödel set theory is related to the Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory. Ilse Novak [5] and Mostowski [8] have shown that, ifCis consistent, thenC′ is consistent. Mostowski has also proved the stronger result that any theorem ofC′ which can be formalized inCis a theorem ofC.The proofs of Novak and Mostowski do not provide a direct method for obtaining a contradiction inCfrom a contradiction inC′. We could, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  27. Socially Distributed Cognition and the Epistemology of Testimony.Joseph Shieber - 2019 - In Miranda Fricker, Peter Graham, David Henderson & Nikolaj Jang Pedersen (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Social Epistemology. New York, USA: Routledge. pp. 87-95.
    Most discussions of the epistemology of testimony include personalist requirements. These include either requirements that stipulate certain features that individual testifiers must have in order to count as transmitters of knowledge, or that stipulate certain features that individual recipients of testimony must have in order to count as acquiring knowledge on the basis of that testimony. For example, in the former case, many views require that testifiers be competent and honest, whereas, in the latter case, many views require that recipients (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. Anti-realism untouched.Joseph Melia - 1991 - Mind 100 (3):341-342.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  29.  71
    Structuralism and scientific realism.Joseph D. Sneed - 1983 - Erkenntnis 19 (1-3):345 - 370.
  30.  38
    Maxwell on the logic of dynamical explanation.Joseph Turner - 1956 - Philosophy of Science 23 (1):36-47.
    In the course of his researches in electromagnetism and the kinetic theory of gases, James Clerk Maxwell gave some thought to the nature of science itself. His observations in this field are of interest today not only because they are his, but because they are still instructive. Maxwell's views are to be found in the many asides with which he enlivened his scientific papers and treatises and in the various articles and reviews which he prepared for more popular consumption. The (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  31.  72
    Husserlian phenomenology and scientific realism.Joseph Rouse - 1987 - Philosophy of Science 54 (2):222-232.
    Husserl's (1970) discussion of "Galilean science" is often dismissed as naïvely instrumentalist and hostile to science. He has been explicitly criticized for misunderstanding idealization in science, for treating the lifeworld as a privileged conceptual framework, and for denying that science can in principle completely describe the world (because ordinary prescientific concepts are irreplaceable). I clarify Husserl's position concerning realism, and use this to show that the first two criticisms depend upon misinterpretations. The third criticism is well taken. Nevertheless, this is (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  32.  59
    Von Neumann's argument for the projection postulate.Joseph D. Sneed - 1966 - Philosophy of Science 33 (1/2):22-39.
    Much of the recent discussion of problematic aspects of quantum-mechanical measurement centers around that feature of quantum theory which is called "the projection postulate." This is roughly the claim that a change of a certain sort occurs in the state of a physical system when a measurement is made on the system. In this paper an argument for the projection postulate due to von Neumann is considered. Attention is focused on trying to provide an understanding of the notion of "the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  33. Robust relativism.Joseph Margolis - 1976 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 35 (1):37-46.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  34.  47
    Default nominal inflection in Hebrew: evidence for mental variables.Joseph Shimron, Iris Berent & Stephen Pinker - 1999 - Cognition 72 (1):1-44.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35. Farewell to Danto and Goodman.Joseph Margolis - 1998 - British Journal of Aesthetics 38 (4):353-374.
  36.  90
    Merleau-ponty and the existential conception of science.Joseph Rouse - 1986 - Synthese 66 (2):249 - 272.
  37.  75
    New philosophies of science in north America — twenty years later.Joseph Rouse - 1998 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 29 (1):71-122.
    This survey of major developments in North American philosophy of science begins with the mid-1960s consolidation of the disciplinary synthesis of internalist history and philosophy of science (HPS) as a response to criticisms of logical empiricism. These developments are grouped for discussion under the following headings: historical metamethodologies, scientific realisms, philosophies of the special sciences, revivals of empiricism, cognitivist naturalisms, social epistemologies, feminist theories of science, studies of experiment and the disunity of science, and studies of science as practice and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  38.  61
    The autographic nature of the dance.Joseph Margolis - 1981 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 39 (4):419-427.
  39. Explanation, prediction, description, and information theory.Joseph F. Hanna - 1969 - Synthese 20 (3):308 - 334.
    The distinction between explanation and prediction has received much attention in recent literature, but the equally important distinction between explanation and description (or between prediction and description) remains blurred. This latter distinction is particularly important in the social sciences, where probabilistic models (or theories) often play dual roles as explanatory and descriptive devices. The distinction between explanation (or prediction) and description is explicated in the present paper in terms of information theory. The explanatory (or predictive) power of a probabilistic model (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  40.  57
    A new approach to the formulation and testing of learning models.Joseph F. Hanna - 1966 - Synthese 16 (3-4):344 - 380.
    It is argued that current attempts to model human learning behavior commonly fail on one of two counts: either the model assumptions are artificially restricted so as to permit the application of mathematical techniques in deriving their consequences, or else the required complex assumptions are imbedded in computer programs whose technical details obscure the theoretical content of the model. The first failing is characteristic of so-called mathematical models of learning, while the second is characteristic of computer simulation models. An approach (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  41.  47
    The transcendental necessity of morality.Joseph Heath - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (2):378–395.
    David Gauthier tries to defend morality by showing that rational agents would choose to adopt a fundamental choice disposition that permits them to cooperate in prisoner's dilemmas. In this paper, I argue that Gauthier, rather than trying to work out a prudential justification for his favored choice disposition, should opt for a transcendental justification. I argue that the disposition in question is the product of socialization, not rational choice. However, only agents who are socialized in such a way that they (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  42.  75
    Chemical "substances" that are not "chemical substances".Sr Joseph E. Earley - 2006 - Philosophy of Science 73 (5):841-852.
    The main scientific problems of chemical bonding were solved half a century ago, but adequate philosophical understanding of chemical combination is yet to be achieved. Chemists routinely use important terms ("element," "atom," "molecule," "substance") with more than one meaning. This can lead to misunderstandings. Eliminativists claim that what seems to be a baseball breaking a window is merely the action of "atoms, acting in concert." They argue that statues, baseballs, and similar macroscopic things "do not exist." When macroscopic objects like (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43. Got to have soul.Joseph A. Baltimore - 2006 - Religious Studies 42 (4):417-430.
    Kevin Corcoran offers an account of how one can be a physicalist about human persons, deny temporal gaps in the existence of persons, and hold that there is an afterlife. I argue that Corcoran's account both violates the necessity of metaphysical identity and implausibly makes an individual's existence dependent on factors wholly extrinsic to the individual. Corcoran's defence is considered, as well as Stephen Davis's suggestions on how an account like Corcoran's can defend itself against these concerns. It is shown, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44. Cohen, Laurence Jonathan.Joseph Shieber - 2005 - In Stuart Brown (ed.), The Dictionary of Twentieth-Century British Philosophers: M-Z. Bristol, England: Thoemmes Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Polanyi, Michael.Joseph Shieber - 2005 - In Stuart Brown (ed.), The Dictionary of Twentieth-Century British Philosophers: M-Z. Bristol, England: Thoemmes Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. The Epistemic Centrality of Testimony and the Coherence of Epistemological Coherentism.Joseph Shieber - 2002 - In Yves Bouchard (ed.), Perspectives on Coherentism. Editions du Scribe.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  10
    Can we have an international dance?Joseph T. Shipley - 1945 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 4 (1):29-31.
  48.  70
    On the tenability of non-factualism with regard to the a priori.Joseph Shieber - 1999 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 80 (4):379–390.
    In a number of recent articles, Hartry Field has attempted to reclaim the a priori for his own brand of non‐factualist epistemology by introducing a non‐epistemic notion of the a priori based purely upon the position of individual beliefs within belief systems. In this article we examine (i) whether a robust enough notion of aprioricity is available to Field, and, by extension, to the radical empiricist and (ii) whether it is possible to connect up the non‐epistemic notion of aprioricity with (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  6
    Critical notices.Joseph Needham - 1930 - Mind 39 (154):221-226.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50.  47
    Why actor models are integral to structural analysis.Joseph M. Whitmeyer - 1994 - Sociological Theory 12 (2):153-165.
    Some versions of structuralism consider actors to be necessary for structural analysis; others argue that they are not. All versions of structuralism consider social structure to be analytically independent of actors. I show through examples and subsequently through deduction that this position is wrong. That is, any conceptualization of social structure necessarily involves a conception of its constituent actors. Moreover, I generalize this point to argue that the structure of scientific knowledge follows a multilevel modeling approach: theory at every level (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 985