Results for ' justice and doctrine of the mean and Aristotle's solution'

999 found
Order:
  1.  11
    Justice.Charles M. Young - 2008 - In Georgios Anagnostopoulos (ed.), A Companion to Aristotle. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 457–470.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction Preliminaries Universal vs. Particular Justice The Scope of Particular Justice Justice and the Doctrine of the Mean: The Problem Distributive and Corrective Justice Political Justice Pleonexia Justice and the Doctrine of the Mean: Aristotle's Solution Conclusion Bibliography.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  48
    The doctrine of the mean in Aristotle's ethical and political theory.I. Evrigenis - 1999 - History of Political Thought 20 (3):393-416.
    The purpose of this paper is to examine the exposition of the doctrine of the mean in the ethical treatises and to determine the role and scope of mesotes within Aristotle's ethical and political theory. The examination of mesotes will reveal the strong connections, for Aristotle, between man, the city, experience, prudence, excellence and eudaimonia. Ultimately, the doctrine of the mean is, in the words of L.W. Rosenfield, an ‘analytical concept’, a component instrumental to (...) theory. Moreover, Aristotle's ethical and political theory is in accordance with the prescriptions of the doctrine of the mean. This is shown through an examination of the thesis, structure and main examples of the Politics, all of which are manifestations of Aristotle's recommendations in his exposition of the doctrine of the mean. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Islamic Ethics and the Doctrine of the Mean.Hossein Atrak - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Investigations at University of Tabriz 8 (14):131-147.
    Originally introduced by Plato and Aristotle, the doctrine of the mean is the most prevalent theory of ethics among Islamic scholars. According to this doctrine, every virtue or excellence of character lies in the observance of the mean, whereas vices are the excess or deficiency of the soul in his functions. Islamic scholars have been influenced by the doctrine, but they have also developed and re-conceptualized it in innovative ways. Kindi, Miskawayh, Avicenna, Raghib Isfahani, Nasir (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  44
    Aristotle's justice.Charles M. Young - 2006 - In Richard Kraut (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 179--197.
    The prelims comprise: Preliminaries Universal vs Particular Justice The Scope of Particular Justice Justice and the Doctrine of the Mean:The Problem Distributive and Corrective Justice Reciprocity Grace Political Justice Pleonexia Justice and the Doctrine of the Mean: Aristotle's Solution Responsibility Conclusion References Further reading.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5. Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean.J. O. Urmson - 1973 - American Philosophical Quarterly 10 (3):223 - 230.
    Aristotle's doctrine of the mean is not a counsel to perform mean or moderate actions. It states that excellence of character is a mean state with regard to the having and displaying of emotions. All emotions are morally neutral; character is shown by displaying emotions on the right occasions, Not too often or too rarely, Not too strongly or too weakly, For sufficient and only sufficient reasons, Etc. The difficulties for such a view presented by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  6.  30
    The Archer and Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Mean.Glen Koehn - 2012 - Peitho 3 (1):155-168.
    It is sometimes claimed that Aristotle’s doctrine of the Mean is false or unhelpful: moral virtues are not typically flanked by two opposing vices as he claimed. However, an explicit restatement of Aristotle’s view in terms of sufficiency for an objective reveals that the Mean is more widely applicable than has sometimes been alleged. Understood as a special case of sufficiency, it is essential to many judgments of right and wrong. I consider some objections by Rosalind Hursthouse (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7. The central doctrine of the mean.Rosalind Hursthouse - 2006 - In Richard Kraut (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 96--115.
    The prelims comprise: The Doctrine of the Mean outside Aristotle's Ethical Works The “Mean” in Action and Feeling The Central Doctrine of the Mean Virtue as a Mean Disposition and the Moral Education of the Passions Acknowledgments References Further reading.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  8. Courage, the Doctrine of the Mean, and the Possibility of Evaluative and Emotional Coherence.Michael Stocker - 1989 - In Plural and conflicting values. New York: Oxford University Press.
    According to Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean, virtue and a good life involve a mean of feeling and action. This chapter focuses on David Pear's claim that the Doctrine is conceptually incoherent. It argues that there are serious difficulties in understanding what it could be for courage and its feelings to be in a mean. Courage involves plural and incommensurable values, victory and danger, and the respective emotions, confidence and fear––it is difficult to see (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  40
    A Plausible Doctrine of the Mean.Jeffrey J. Fisher - 2018 - Review of Metaphysics 72 (1):53-75.
    While Aristotle is often lauded, especially by virtue ethicists, for his focus on and insight into virtue, a central aspect of his conception of virtue—the doctrine of the mean—is often derided as false if not indeed absurd. The reason for this disparity in reaction to Aristotle is that the doctrine of the mean has been severely misinterpreted as stating that there are a variety of parameters in which one must achieve a mean. Such a (...) is false, but it is not Aristotle’s. In this paper, the author gives a more accurate account of the doctrine of the mean than has heretofore been given. According to this account, the doctrine simply states that virtue disposes one to feel one’s passions with an appropriate intensity. The author closes by considering Hursthouse’s famous criticisms of the doctrine of the mean, and he shows that they fail to be reasons for rejecting the doctrine. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10. Political Justice in Aristotle's "Nicomachean Ethics" and "Politics".Thornton C. Lockwood - 2004 - Dissertation, Boston University
    In the center of the fifth book of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle elliptically characterizes political justice as a form of reciprocal rule that exists between free and equal persons pursuing a common life directed toward self-sufficiency under the rule of law. My dissertation analyzes Aristotle's thematic treatments of political justice in the Nicomachean Ethics and Politics in order to elucidate its meaning, clarify its relationship to the other forms of justice that he also discusses, and compare (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Plato’s Metaphysical Development before Middle Period Dialogues.Mohammad Bagher Ghomi - manuscript
    Regarding the relation of Plato’s early and middle period dialogues, scholars have been divided to two opposing groups: unitarists and developmentalists. While developmentalists try to prove that there are some noticeable and even fundamental differences between Plato’s early and middle period dialogues, the unitarists assert that there is no essential difference in there. The main goal of this article is to suggest that some of Plato’s ontological as well as epistemological principles change, both radically and fundamentally, between the early and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  11
    The Inchoatio formarum sensibilium _ in Albert the Great’s Commentary on Aristotle’s _De sensu et sensato.Roberto Zambiasi - 2023 - Quaestio 23:267-284.
    The doctrine of the inchoatio formae is an important feature of Albert the Great’s metaphysics and natural philosophy, as modern scholars, starting at least with Bruno Nardi’s pioneering study, have recognised. Nevertheless, the notion of the inchoatio formae as employed by Albert is usually understood to refer exclusively to the relationship between matter and substantial forms. On the contrary, in his commentary on Aristotle’s De sensu et sensato, and specifically in the context of a discussion of the so-called issue (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Defending the Doctrine of the Mean Against Counterexamples: A General Strategy.Nicholas Colgrove - 2024 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly (Online First):1-24.
    Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean states that each moral virtue stands opposed to two types of vice: one of excess and one of deficiency, respectively. Critics claim that some virtues—like honesty, fair-mindedness, and patience—are counterexamples to Aristotle’s doctrine. Here, I develop a generalizable strategy to defend the doctrine of the mean against such counterexamples. I argue that not only is the doctrine of the mean defensible, but taking it seriously also allows us to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  60
    On the Quantitative Doctrine of the Mean.Joe Mintoff - 2013 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 51 (4):445-464.
    Aristotle's doctrine of the mean is expressed in quantitative terms, but this has been hard for some people to take literally, its more elaborate versions sometimes being described as “extremely silly.” Roughly two books of the Nicomachean Ethics are permeated with talk of character traits which are either deficient or excessive, however, and the aim of this paper is to examine how the doctrine might meet the objections of its critics.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  50
    Justice in Islamic Philosophical Ethics: Miskawayh's Mediating Contribution.Majid Fakhry - 1975 - Journal of Religious Ethics 3 (2):243 - 254.
    The author examines the development of the concept of justice in Arabic philosophical ethics, which culminates in the attempt by Miskawayh to harmonize Plato's concept of what it means to be just with Aristotle's concept of acting justly. Miskawayh's contribution, which draws upon Neo-Platonic and Stoic authors of late antiquity, is shown to shed light on possible modes of interpreting the ethical doctrines of Plato and Aristotle and even to point the way to the solution of some (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  48
    Aristotle's Teleology and Uexküll's Theory of Living Nature.Helene Weiss - 1948 - Classical Quarterly 42 (1-2):44-.
    The purpose of this paper is to draw attention to a similarity between an ancient and a modern theory of living nature. There is no need to present the Aristotelian doctrine in full detail. I must rather apologize for repeating much that is well known. My endeavour is to offer it for comparison, and, incidentally, to clear it from misrepresentation. Uexküll's theory, on the other hand, is little known, and what is given here is an insufficient outline of it. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  52
    The Doctrine of the Mean in Aristotle's Rhetoric.Lawrence W. Rosenfield - 1965 - Theoria 31 (3):191-198.
  18.  41
    Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean and the Circularity of Human Nature.Nahum Brown - 2016 - Kritike 10 (2):122-131.
    Aristotle's famous claim that human beings are animals with rationality has a subtle and complicated articulation in his doctrine of the mean. This paper offers textual analysis of Aristotle's discussion of the mean as a resource for coming to terms with the thesis that humans naturally deliberate over the essence of their nature. Unlike other animals who tend to act without deliberation and without mediation, human beings are the animals who are capable of giving an (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  36
    The Meaning of "Aristotelianism" in Medieval Moral and Political Thought.Cary J. Nederman - 1996 - Journal of the History of Ideas 57 (4):563-585.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Meaning of “Aristotelianism” in Medieval Moral and Political ThoughtCary J. NedermanI. “Aristotelian” and “Aristotelianism” are words that students of medieval ideas use constantly and almost inescapably. 1 The widespread usage of these terms by scholars in turn reflects the popularity of Aristotle’s thought itself during the Latin Middle Ages: Aristotle provided many of the raw materials with which educated Christians of the Middle Ages built up the edifice (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20. John Calvin and Virtue Ethics: Augustinian and Aristotelian Themes.David S. Sytsma - 2020 - Journal of Religious Ethics 48 (3):519-556.
    Many scholars have argued that the Protestant Reformation generally departed from virtue ethics, and this claim is often accepted by Protestant ethicists. This essay argues against such discontinuity by demonstrating John Calvin’s reception of ethical concepts from Augustine and Aristotle. Calvin drew on Augustine’s concept of eudaimonia and many aspects of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics , including concepts of choice, habit, virtue as a mean, and the specific virtues of justice and prudence. Calvin also evaluated the problem of pagan (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  93
    Grotius and Aristotle: The Justice of Taking Too Little.Andrew Blom - 2016 - History of Political Thought 36 (1):84-112.
    The theory of justice that Hugo Grotius developed in De Jure Belli ac Pacis (The Law of War and Peace, 1625) set itself against a certain reading of Aristotle, according to which justice is conceived of as a mean between taking too much and taking too little. I argue that we can best understand the implications of Grotius' mature conception by considering the ends to which he had deployed this Aristotelian notion in his earlier work. Grotius came (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  10
    The Problem of Universal Judgments in Aristotle’s Ethics.R. S. Platonov - 2018 - Russian Journal of Philosophical Sciences 10:81-96.
    The author sets a goal to show the specificity of the formulation of universal prescriptive judgments about a virtuous act in the framework of Aristotelian ethical doctrine. To achieve this goal, Aristotle’s philosophy concept of practical wisdom is analyzed. It shows a necessity to distinguish the use of practical wisdom in a personal experience of the act and for forming the inter-subjective practical knowledge about making of a virtuous act. The specificity of ethics as practical knowledge and its difference (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  22
    Distinguishing the Public from the Private: Aristotle's Solution to Plato's Paradox.R. Zhu - 2004 - History of Political Thought 25 (2):231-242.
    By emphasizing that a political entity is a communal partnership, Aristotle implies that Plato’s city is not yet bona fide political. Due to his reluctance to draw a clear distinction between the private and public realms, Plato’s political theory tries to meet conflicting demands. By examining his solution to Plato’s paradox, we will be able to appreciate the peculiar relation between Aristotle’s political justice and justice per se, and the political significance of Aristotle’s distinction between the public (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. Meaning and Reference in Aristotle’s Concept of the Linguistic Sign.Ludovic De Cuypere & Klaas Willems - 2008 - Foundations of Science 13 (3-4):307-324.
    To Aristotle, spoken words are symbols, not of objects in the world, but of our mental experiences related to these objects. Presently there are two major strands of interpretation of Aristotle’s concept of the linguistic sign. First, there is the structuralist account offered by Coseriu (Geschichte der Sprachphilosophie. Von den Anfängen bis Rousseau, 2003 [1969], pp. 65–108) whose interpretation is reminiscent of the Saussurean sign concept. A second interpretation, offered by Lieb (in: Geckeler (Ed.) Logos Semantikos: Studia Linguistica in Honorem (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  56
    Aristotle’s Conception of Ethical and Natural Virtue: How the Unity Thesis sheds light on the Doctrine of the Mean.Anselm Winfried Müller - 2004 - In Matthias Lutz-Bachmann & Jan Szaif (eds.), Was Ist Das Für den Menschen Gute? / What is Good for a Human Being?: Menschliche Natur Und Güterlehre / Human Nature and Values. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 18-53.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  26.  6
    Meaning and Reference in Aristotle’s Concept of the Linguistic Sign.Ludovic Cuypere & Klaas Willems - 2008 - Foundations of Science 13 (3-4):307-324.
    To Aristotle, spoken words are symbols, not of objects in the world, but of our mental experiences related to these objects. Presently there are two major strands of interpretation of Aristotle’s concept of the linguistic sign. First, there is the structuralist account offered by Coseriu (Geschichte der Sprachphilosophie. Von den Anfängen bis Rousseau, 2003 [1969], pp. 65–108) whose interpretation is reminiscent of the Saussurean sign concept. A second interpretation, offered by Lieb (in: Geckeler (Ed.) Logos Semantikos: Studia Linguistica in Honorem (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. Aristotle's Doctrine of Justice and the Law of Athens.Peter Kussmaul - 2008 - Dionysius 26.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  35
    The Four Books: Confucian Analects, the Great Learning, the Doctrine of the Mean, and the Works of Mencius.E. H. S. & James Legge - 1966 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 86 (2):263.
  29.  22
    Iv physiology and the doctrine of the mean in Aristotle.Theodore James Tracy - 1969 - In Physiological theory and the doctrine of the mean in Plato and Aristotle. The Hague,: Mouton. pp. 157-333.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  77
    Breve storia dell'etica.Sergio Cremaschi - 2012 - Roma RM, Italia: Carocci.
    The book reconstructs the history of Western ethics. The approach chosen focuses the endless dialectic of moral codes, or different kinds of ethos, moral doctrines that are preached in order to bring about a reform of existing ethos, and ethical theories that have taken shape in the context of controversies about the ethos and moral doctrines as means of justifying or reforming moral doctrines. Such dialectic is what is meant here by the phrase ‘moral traditions’, taken as a name for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  31. Doctrines of the Mean and the Debate Concerning Skills in Fourth-Century Medicine, Rhetoric and Ethics.D. S. Hutchinson - 1988 - Apeiron 21 (2):17 - 52.
  32.  44
    Revealing the Dao of Heaven through the Dao of humans: Sincerity in The Doctrine of the Mean.Chen Yun - 2009 - Frontiers of Philosophy in China 4 (4):537-551.
    In Zhongyong 中庸 (The Doctrine of the Mean), cheng 诚 (sincerity) is the “Dao of all Daos”, the “virtue of all virtues”, and thus connects the Dao of humans and that of Heaven. The Dao of humans can reveal the sincerity in the Dao of Heaven in two approaches: to contemplate on sincerity and to conduct in sincerity. Meanwhile, sincerity in the Dao of Heaven is unfolded in everything’s seeking for its own nature and destiny, thus the most (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  18
    Aristotle's Theory of Substance : The Categories and Metaphysics Zeta: The Categories and Metaphysics Zeta.Michael V. Wedin - 2000 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Aristotle's views on the fundamental nature of reality are usually taken to be inconsistent. The two main sources for these views are the Categories and the central books of the Metaphysics, particularly book Zeta. In the early theory of the Categories the basic entities of the world are concrete objects such as Socrates: Aristotle calls them 'primary substances'. But the later theory awards this title to the forms of concrete objects. Michael Wedin proposes a compatibilist solution to this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34.  5
    Toward a Critical Synthesis of the Aristotelian and Confucian Doctrines of the Mean.Kevin M. Brien - 2020 - Dialogue and Universalism 30 (1):9-35.
    This paper is the second phase of a project that was begun more than three years ago. The first phase culminated in the publication of a paper working toward a critical appropriation of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.1 Therein Aristotle famously argues that human wellbeing (eudaimonia) is constituted by “activity of the soul in accordance with moral and intellectual virtue.”2 This earlier paper brought into focus all the main lines of Aristotle’s theoretical web in the N. Ethics: including the nature of the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  30
    The Tyrant’s Progress: The Meaning of ΤΥΡΑΝΝΟΣ in Plato and Aristotle.Edmund Stewart - 2021 - Polis 38 (2):208-236.
    This article considers a longstanding problem: what does the word τύραννος mean? And if it means ‘bad / tyrannical ruler’, why are good rulers called tyrants? The solution proposed here is that tyranny is not a fixed state of being, or not being, but instead a gradual process of development. To be called a tyrant, a ruler need not embody all the stereotypical traits of tyranny. If tyranny is, by definition, unconstitutional and illegitimate rule, then there may be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Pt. 1. ancient philosophy and faith, from athens to jerusalem: Lecture 1. introductIon to the problems and scope of philosophy ; lecture 2. the old testament, guest lecture / by Robert Oden ; lecture 3. the gospels of mark and Matthew, guest lecture / by Elizabeth mcnamer ; lecture 4. Paul, his world, guest lecture / by Elizabeth mcnamer ; lecture 5. presocratics, Ionian speculaton and eleatic metaphysics ; lecture 6. republic I, justice, power, and knowledge ; lecture 7. republic II-v, Paul and city ; lecture 8. republic VI-x, the architecture of reality ; lecture 9. Aristotle's metaphysical views ; lecture 10. Aristotle's politics, the golden mean and just rule, guest lecture. [REVIEW]Dennis Dalton, the stoic ideal lecture 11Marcus Aurelius' Meditations & lecture 12Augustine'S. City of God - 2000 - In Darren Staloff, Louis Markos, Jeremy duQuesnay Adams, Phillip Cary, Dennis Dalton, Alan Charles Kors, Jeremy Shearmur, Robert C. Solomon, Robert Kane, Kathleen Marie Higgins, Mark W. Risjord & Douglas Kellner (eds.), Great Minds of the Western Intellectual Tradition. Teaching Co..
  37.  19
    Aristotle’s Theory of Substance: The Categories and Metaphysics Zeta.Michael V. Wedin - 2000 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Aristotle's views on the fundamental nature of reality are usually taken to be inconsistent. The two main sources for these views are the Categories and the central books of the Metaphysics, particularly book Zeta. In the early theory of the Categories the basic entities of the world are concrete objects such as Socrates: Aristotle calls them 'primary substances'. But the later theory awards this title to the forms of concrete objects. Michael Wedin proposes a compatibilist solution to this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38.  41
    The Commandment against the Law: Writing and Divine Justice in Walter Benjamin's "Critique of Violence".Tracy McNulty - 2007 - Diacritics 37 (2/3):34-60.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Commandment against the Law Writing and Divine Justice in Walter Benjamin’s “Critique of Violence”Tracy McNulty (bio)Pierre Legendre has shown that the Romano-canonical legal traditions that form the foundations of Western jurisprudence “are founded in a discourse which denies the essential quality of the relation of the body to writing” [“Masters of Law” 110]. It emerges historically as a repudiation of Jewish legalism and Talmud law, where the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39. Filozofia praw człowieka. Prawa człowieka w świetle ich międzynarodowej ochrony.Marek Piechowiak - 1999 - Lublin: Towarzystwo Naukowe KUL.
    PHILOSOPHY OF HUMAN RIGHTS: HUMAN RIGHTS IN LIGHT OF THEIR INTERNATIONAL PROTECTION Summary The book consists of two main parts: in the first, on the basis of an analysis of international law, elements of the contemporary conception of human rights and its positive legal protection are identified; in the second - in light of the first part -a philosophical theory of law based on the tradition leading from Plato, Aristotle, and St. Thomas Aquinas is constructed. The conclusion contains an application (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  58
    The Virtues of Aristotle’s Ethics.Paula Gottlieb - 2009 - Cambridge University Press.
    While Aristotle's account of the happy life continues to receive attention, many of his claims about virtue of character seem so puzzling that modern philosophers have often discarded them, or have reworked them to fit more familiar theories that do not make virtue of character central. In this book, Paula Gottlieb takes a fresh look at Aristotle's claims, particularly the much-maligned doctrine of the mean. She shows how they form a thought-provoking ethic of virtue, one that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  41.  56
    Blind-Spots in Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Perceptual Mean.Roberto Grasso - 2020 - Apeiron 53 (3):257-284.
    This paper aims to identify several interpretive problems posed by the final part of DA II.11, where Aristotle intertwines the thesis that a sense is like a ‘mean’ and an explanation for the existence of a ‘blind spot’ related to the sense of touch, adding the further contention that we are capable of discriminating because the mean ‘becomes the other opposite’ in relation to the perceptible property being perceived. To solve those problems, the paper explores a novel interpretation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42. Peter Lombard on the doctrine of creation: A discussion of sentences Bk II, D. 1, C. 1-3.Brandon Zimmerman - 2019 - The Australasian Catholic Record 96 (1):83.
    The purpose of this brief study is to ascertain Peter Lombard's understanding of what the Christian doctrine of creation means and his judgment about whether pagan philosophers were able to reach this doctrine through the light of natural reason. Lombard's views on creation set the foundation for thirteenth-century discussions of creation, since all the scholastic masters of Oxford and Paris commented on Lombard's 'Sentences' and thus recorded their agreement or disagreement with him. Lombard's views are of especial importance (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. The Rafī’ee-Qazvīnī’s Solution to the Sadrāian Problem of Return.Mohammad Ahmadizadeh & Mohammad Kazem Forghani - 2013 - پژوهشنامه فلسفه دین 11 (1):79-97.
    According to the principles of transcendent philosophy, the human soul as a contingent existence after being created in this world has a continuous motion from an actuality to another one until becoming immaterial. This means that he leaves his body and continues to his evolution immaterially. According to the principle of “Impossibility of Return” it seems impossible for human being to return to the mundane life after his death. This belief is apparently inconsistent with the Islamic doctrine of “dead (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  11
    The Doctrine of the Soul in Aristotle’s Lost Dialogue “On Philosophy”.Anton-Hermann Chroust - 1968 - New Scholasticism 42 (3):364-373.
  45.  64
    Physiological theory and the doctrine of the mean in Plato and Aristotle.Theodore James Tracy - 1969 - The Hague,: Mouton.
  46.  29
    The Meaning of ‘Ο λόγοσ τῆσ οὐσίασ in Aristotle’s Categories 1a.John P. Anton - 1968 - The Monist 52 (2):252 - 267.
    The purpose of this paper is to inquire into the meaning of the troublesome Aristotelian expression ‘Ο λόγοσ τῆσ οὐσίασ as it occurs at the very opening of Categories 1a 1–2, 7. That the passage has presented serious difficulties to commentators and translators alike can be easily ascertained through a survey and comparison of the relevant literature. It would seem from the disagreements among translators that the passage is either vague in the original Greek or that Aristotle did not have (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  41
    When organizations are too good: Applying Aristotle's doctrine of the mean to the corporate ethical virtues model.Muel Kaptein - 2017 - Business Ethics: A European Review 26 (3):300-311.
    Aristotle's doctrine of the mean states that a virtue is the mean state between two vices: a deficient and an excessive one. The Corporate Ethical Virtues Model defines the mean and the corresponding deficient vice for each of its seven virtues. This paper defines for each of these virtues the corresponding excessive vice and explores why organizations characterized by these excessive vices increase the likelihood that their employees will behave unethically. The excessive vices are patronization, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  48. Mediality and Rationality in Aristotle's Account of Excellence of Character.Mark McCullagh - 1995 - Apeiron 28 (4):155 - 174.
    I offer a reading of Aristotle’s “doctrine of the mean” that avoids two pitfalls: taking it as truistic, and taking it as involving the bizarre thesis that whenever one acts as reason directs, one’s action is mid-way between some extremes. The crucial point is that while Aristotle denies the existence of useful general ethical truths, he himself offers truths about the likelihoods with which rationality will require actions of certain types; and it is with such truths that the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  13
    The Meaning of ‘Ο λόγοσ τῆσ οὐσίασ in Aristotle’s Categories 1a.John P. Anton - 1968 - The Monist 52 (2):252-267.
    The purpose of this paper is to inquire into the meaning of the troublesome Aristotelian expression ‘Ο λόγοσ τῆσ οὐσίασ as it occurs at the very opening of Categories 1a 1–2, 7. That the passage has presented serious difficulties to commentators and translators alike can be easily ascertained through a survey and comparison of the relevant literature. It would seem from the disagreements among translators that the passage is either vague in the original Greek or that Aristotle did not have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  48
    Aristotle’s Contrary Psychology: The Mean in Ethics and Beyond.Louis Groarke - 2015 - Review of Metaphysics 69 (1):47-71.
    Contemporary commentators such as Rosalind Hursthouse misconstrue Aristotle’s doctrine of the ethical mean. They propose a monist account of his moral psychology, explaining each virtue in terms of the presence or absence of a single psychological trait. In contrast, the author argues that Aristotle depicts virtue as a balancing of two opposed psychological inclinations that push and pull in different directions. Each inclination is a positive force in its own right; neither is mere privation. This dualistic account of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 999