Results for 'nonmedical exemptions'

857 found
Order:
  1.  27
    Making salient ethics arguments about vaccine mandates: A California case study.Mark C. Navin & Katie Attwell - 2023 - Bioethics 37 (9):854-861.
    Vaccine mandates can take many forms, and different kinds of mandates can implicate an array of values in diverse ways. It follows that good ethics arguments about particular vaccine mandates will attend to the details of individual policies. Furthermore, attention to particular mandate policies—and to attributes of the communities they aim to govern—can also illuminate which ethics arguments may be more salient in particular contexts. If ethicists want their arguments to make a difference in policy, they should attend to these (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  11
    School staff as vaccine advocates: Perspectives on vaccine mandates and the student registration process.Mark Christopher Navin, Aaron Scherer, Ethan Bradley & Katie Attwell - 2023 - Vaccine 41 (5):1169-1175.
    Recently, several states in the US have made it more difficult to receive nonmedical exemptions to school vaccine mandates in the hope of better orienting parents towards vaccination. However, little is known about how public-facing school staff implement and enforce mandate policies, including why or how often they steer parents towards nonmedical exemptions. This study focused on Michigan, which has recently added an additional burden for families seeking nonmedical exemptions. We used an anonymous online (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  53
    An Ethical Analysis of Mandatory Influenza Vaccination of Health Care Personnel: Implementing Fairly and Balancing Benefits and Burdens.Armand H. Matheny Antommaria - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (9):30-37.
    Health care institutions have paid increasing attention to preventing nosocomial transmission of influenza through vaccination of health care personnel. While multifaceted voluntary interventions have increased vaccination rates, proponents of mandatory programs contend the rates remain unacceptably low. Conventional bioethical analyses of mandatory programs are inadequate; they fail to account for the obligations of nonprofessional personnel or to justify the weights assigned to different ethical principles. Using an ethics framework for public health permits a fuller analysis. The framework's focus on fairness (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  4.  13
    An Ethical Analysis of Mandatory Influenza Vaccination of Health Care Personnel: Implementing Fairly and Balancing Benefits and Burdens.Armand Matheny Antommaria - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (9):30-37.
    Health care institutions have paid increasing attention to preventing nosocomial transmission of influenza through vaccination of health care personnel. While multifaceted voluntary interventions have increased vaccination rates, proponents of mandatory programs contend the rates remain unacceptably low. Conventional bioethical analyses of mandatory programs are inadequate; they fail to account for the obligations of nonprofessional personnel or to justify the weights assigned to different ethical principles. Using an ethics framework for public health permits a fuller analysis. The framework's focus on fairness (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  5. Perspectives of Public Health Nurses on the Ethics of Mandated Vaccine Education.Mark Christopher Navin, Andrea T. Kozak & Michael J. Deem - 2020 - Nursing Outlook 68 (1):62-72.
    Background Since 2015, Michigan has required parents who request nonmedical exemptions (NMEs) from school or daycare immunization mandates to receive education from local public health staff (usually nurses). This is unlike most other US states that have implemented mandatory immunization counseling, which require physicians to document immunization education, or which provide online instruction. -/- Purpose To attend to the activity and dispositions of the public health staff who provide “waiver education”. -/- Method This study reports results of focus (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  17
    The Measles and Free Riders.Katharine Browne - 2016 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 25 (3):472-478.
    :This article takes up a game-theoretic perspective on California’s recently passed bill that closes all nonmedical exemptions for school-mandated vaccination. Such a perspective characterizes parental decisions to vaccinate their children as a collective action problem and reveals the presence of an incentive to free ride—to enjoy the benefits of others’ efforts to vaccinate their children without vaccinating one’s own. This article defends California’s legislation as a reasonable means of overcoming the free rider problem and of ensuring that the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  33
    Dismissal Policies for Vaccine Refusal -- A Reply.Michael J. Deem, Mark Christopher Navin & John D. Lantos - 2018 - JAMA Pediatrics 172 (11):1101-1102.
    Marshall and O’Leary’s thoughtful response to our article suggests that dismissal policies are ethically justifiable because they might induce parents to immunize their children. This outcome is conceivable, but we have only anecdotes about how often it occurs. Such evidence became the thin reed on which the American Academy of Pediatrics rested its new policy of tolerating the practice of dismissing vaccine-hesitant parents. It seems likely that relatively few parents would agree to vaccinate because they were threatened with dismissal. Other (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  9
    An Ethical Analysis of Hospital Visitor Restrictions and Masking Requirements During the COVID-19 Pandemic.Joshua K. Schaffzin, Laura Monhollen & Armand H. Matheny Antommaria - 2021 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 32 (1):38-47.
    Nonpharmaceutical interventions to minimize the transmission of the severe acute respiratory syndrome coronavirus 2 are necessary because we currently lack a vaccine or specific treatments. Healthcare facilities have adopted visitor restrictions and masking requirements. These interventions should be evaluated as public health measures, focusing on their efficacy, the availability of less-restrictive alternatives, and the minimization of the burdens and their balance with the benefits. These interventions, as well as exceptions, can be justified by the same analysis. For example, visitor restrictions (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9. Mélanges.Étude Sur L'histoire des Exemptions - 1900 - Revue D’Histoire Ecclésiastique 1:472.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  67
    The exemption that confirms the rule: Reflections on proceduralism and the uk hybrid embryos controversy.Enzo Rossi - 2009 - Res Publica 15 (3):237-250.
    This paper provides an interpretation of the licensing provisions envisaged under the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act 1990 as a model for a rule and exemption-based procedural strategy for the adjudication of potential ethical controversies, and it offers an account of the liberal-democratic legitimacy of the procedure’s outcomes as well as of the legal procedure itself. Drawing on a novel articulation of the distinction between exceptions and exemptions, the paper argues that such a rule and exemption mechanism, while not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11.  23
    Religious Exemptions.Kevin Vallier & Michael Weber (eds.) - 2018 - Oup Usa.
    Religious exemptions have a long history in American law, but have become especially controversial over the last several years. The essays in this volume address the moral and philosophical issues that the legal practice of religious exemptions often raises.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  15
    Exemptions for Conscience.Simon Căbulea May - 2016 - In Cécile Laborde & Aurélia Bardon (eds.), Religion in Liberal Political Philosophy. New York, NY: oxford university press. pp. 191-203.
    The Moral Conscience principle claims that a conflict between the demands of a law and the demands of an individual’s sincere moral conscience provides her with a defeasible moral entitlement to an exemption. This chapter argues that this principle is vulnerable to an unfairness objection. There is nothing special about moral conscience that would justify granting an exemption, it claims, that is not shared by a variety of non-moral projects. Thus, there is no principled moral reason for a defeasible entitlement (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13. Excuses, exemptions, and derivative norms.Cameron Boult - 2019 - Ratio 32 (2):150-158.
    Distinguishing between excuses and exemptions advances our understanding of a standard range of problem cases in debates about epistemic norms. But it leaves open a problem of accounting for blameless norm violation in ‘prospective agents’. By shifting focus in our theory of excuses from rational excellence to norms governing the dispositions of agents, we can account for a fuller range of normative phenomena at play in debates about epistemic norms.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  14. Justification for Conscience Exemptions in Health Care.Lori Kantymir & Carolyn McLeod - 2013 - Bioethics 27 (8):16-23.
    Some bioethicists argue that conscientious objectors in health care should have to justify themselves, just as objectors in the military do. They should have to provide reasons that explain why they should be exempt from offering the services that they find offensive. There are two versions of this view in the literature, each giving different standards of justification. We show these views are each either too permissive (i.e. would result in problematic exemptions based on conscience) or too restrictive (i.e. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  15. Exemption clauses in trusts.Philip Sales - 2018 - In Paul S. Davies, Simon Douglas & James Goudkamp (eds.), Defences in equity. New York: Hart.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  42
    Religious Exemptions to the Immunization Statutes: Balancing Public Health and Religious Freedom.Lainie Friedman Ross & Timothy J. Aspinwall - 1997 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 25 (2-3):202-209.
    In February 1997, the Committee on Bioethics of the American Academy of Pediatrics updated its position on religious exemptions to medical care. In its earlier statement, the committee noted that forty-four states have religious exemptions to the child abuse and neglect statutes, and they argued for the repeal of these exemptions. The committee did not indude in its statement a position on religious exemptions to childhood immunization requirements that exist in forty-eight states, although this issue was (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  17. Cultural exemptions, expensive tastes, and equal opportunities.Jonathan Quong - 2006 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 23 (1):53–71.
    abstract The most well‐known liberal‐egalitarian defence of cultural rights, provided by Will Kymlicka, presents culture as a primary good, and thus a resource that ought to be distributed according to some fair egalitarian criteria. Kymlicka relies on the intuition that inequalities between persons that are the result of brute luck rather than personal choice are unjust in making the case for various multicultural rights. This article makes two main claims. First, the standard luck egalitarian intuition on which Kymlicka's argument relies (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  18.  88
    Exemptions for whom? On the relevant focus of egalitarian concern.Maria Paola Ferretti - 2009 - Res Publica 15 (3):269-287.
    Granting differential treatment is often considered a way of placing some groups in a better position in order to maintain or improve their cultural, economic, health-related or other conditions, and to address persistent inequalities. Critics of multiculturalism have pointed out the tension between protection for groups and protection for group members. The ‘rule-and-exemption’ approach has generally been conceived as more resistant to such criticism insofar as exemptions are not conceded to minorities or ethical and religious groups as such, but (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  48
    Self-Exempting Conciliationism is Arbitrary.Simon Blessenohl - 2015 - Kriterion - Journal of Philosophy 29 (3):1-22.
    Self-exempting conciliationism is the view that it is rational to give weight to the opinions of peers in disagreement, except in disagreements about how to respond to disagreement. The special treatment of disagreements about disagreement, which is important to avoid self-undermining, seems arbitrary. Two arguments against this objection were put forward. Elga [3] aims to show that there is an independent motivation for conciliationism to be self-exempting. Pittard [5] argues that the special treatment is not arbitrary because the concern for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  70
    The Ethics of Nonmedical Sex Selection.H. Strange & R. Chadwick - 2010 - Health Care Analysis 18 (3):252-266.
    The aim of this paper is to demonstrate that there are significant ethical problems with nonmedical sex selection, and that prohibitive legislation is justified. The central argument put forward is that nonmedical sex selection is a sexist practice which promotes socially restrictive conceptions of sex, gender and family. Several steps are taken to justify this position: background information on technology and legislation is provided, the neoliberal position that is supportive of nonmedical sex selection is described, and preliminary (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  27
    Religious Exemptions to the Immunization Statutes: Balancing Public Health and Religious Freedom.Lainie Friedman Ross & Timothy J. Aspinwall - 1997 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 25 (2-3):202-209.
    In February 1997, the Committee on Bioethics of the American Academy of Pediatrics updated its position on religious exemptions to medical care. In its earlier statement, the committee noted that forty-four states have religious exemptions to the child abuse and neglect statutes, and they argued for the repeal of these exemptions. The committee did not indude in its statement a position on religious exemptions to childhood immunization requirements that exist in forty-eight states, although this issue was (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  22.  2
    Procedural Dimensions of Religious Exemptions to Covid-19 Vaccine Mandates: Promoting Clarity, Fairness, and Transparency in Applications.Hajung Lee - forthcoming - AJOB Empirical Bioethics.
    This study examines the procedural ethical considerations surrounding religious exemptions to Covid vaccine mandates, specifically focusing on immigrant healthcare personnel (HCP) and HCPs of color. It emphasizes communication issues with applicants by investigating exemption applications and their accompanying guidelines. While there is extensive literature on the ethical implications of religious exemptions, a notable gap remains in addressing the procedural aspects of religious exemption applications and their reviewing processes. The study scrutinized religious exemption application forms and accompanying guidelines from (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  13
    Contempt, Futility, and Exemption.Simon Căbulea May - 2018 - In Kevin Vallier & Michael Weber (eds.), Religious Exemptions. Oup Usa. pp. 59-73.
    Exemptions from laws of general application are sometimes granted on the basis of an individual’s unwillingness to comply with the law. Most such volitional exemptions involve a conflict between the law and the demands of an individual’s religious or secular moral convictions. I argue here that a limited number of volitional exemptions can be justified on the basis of a futility principle. When otherwise morally permissible penalties for violating the law cannot be expected to induce the compliance (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  39
    Exemptions, Sincerity and Pastafarianism.Nick Martin - 2019 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 37 (2):258-272.
    ABSTRACT Because Pastafarianism – or the Church of the Flying Spaghetti Monster – is a parodic religion, common sense suggests its ‘adherents’ should not receive exemptions. However, the prima facie case for excluding Pastafarians is complicated by the fact that many assert their religion is as legitimate as any other religion and that their beliefs are genuine. Indeed, Pastafarians have already obtained exemptions in various countries. Taking the dominant liberal egalitarian, integrity‐based approach to exemptions, this article investigates (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  40
    Religious Exemptions: An Egalitarian Demand?Stuart G. White - 2012 - Law and Ethics of Human Rights 6 (1):97-118.
    To what extent does the case for exemptions from laws to accommodate religious commitments rest specifically on egalitarian arguments? To what extent should specifically egalitarian or anti-discrimination concerns be used to determine when such exemptions should be granted? This Article considers both of these questions. It argues that while egalitarian considerations have a role to play in both the general justification and case-by-case evaluation of exemption claims, neither the justification, nor the evaluation of exemptions, properly rests solely (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  65
    Religious exemptions, claims of conscience, and idola fori.Andrei Bespalov - 2020 - Jurisprudence 11 (2):225-242.
    According to the standard liberal egalitarian approach, religious exemptions from generally applicable laws can be justified on the grounds of equal respect for each citizen’s conscience. I contend that claims of conscience cannot justify demands for exemptions, since they do not meet even the most inclusive standards of public justification. Arguments of the form ‘My conscience says so’ do not explicate the rationale behind the practices that the claimants seek to protect. Therefore, such arguments do not constitute even (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  25
    Without Exemptions: Reconciling Equality with the Accommodation of Diversity.Aurélia Bardon - 2023 - Res Publica 29 (3):483-499.
    When generally applicable rules clash with one’s cultural, religious or moral commitments, should exemptions be granted? The debate on exemptions raises the question both of what it means to treat people equally and of what it means to protect diversity adequately. The objective of this paper is to defend the no-exemption argument and to make it a more attractive position for liberals. I first argue that exemptions violate the principle of equal treatment because they rely on distinctions (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  48
    Therapeutic use exemptions and the doctrine of double effect.Jon Pike - 2018 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 45 (1):68-82.
    Without taking a position on the overall justification of anti-doping regulations, I analyse the possible justification of Therapeutic Use Exemptions from such rules. TUEs are a creative way to prevent the unfair exclusion of athletes with a chronic condition, and they have the potential to be the least bad option. But they cannot be competitively neutral. Their justification must rest, instead, on the relevance of intentions to permissibility. I illustrate this by means of a set of thought experiments in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  32
    Execution Exemption Should Be Based on Actual Vulnerability, Not Disability Label.Harvey N. Switzky & Stephen Greenspan - 2003 - Ethics and Behavior 13 (1):19-26.
    Mental retardation is an invented bureaucratic category, currently undergoing radical rethinking and likely renaming, that includes many who have biologically based brain disorders, but is itself determined on functional criteria that are purely arbitrary. People with MR are socially vulnerable and thus are more likely to be "naíve confessors," "naíve defendants," and "naíve offenders." That is most likely the rationale and justification for the Supreme Court's decision, in Atkins v. Virginia, to exempt the class from execution. Although the decision is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  50
    Conscience Exemptions in Medicine: A Hegelian Feminist Perspective.Victoria I. Burke - 2016 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 30 (2):267-287.
    In this article, I defend the view that conscience exemption clauses for medical practitioners (doctors, nurses, technicians, pharmacists) should be limited by patient protection clauses. This view was also defended by Mark Wicclair, in his book on conscience exemptions in medicine (Cambridge UP, 2011). In this article, I defend Wicclair’s view by supplementing it with Hegelian ethical theory and feminist critical theory. Conscience exemptions are important to support as a matter of human rights. They support an individual’s right (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. The Moral Basis of Religious Exemptions.Kevin Vallier - 2016 - Law and Philosophy 35 (1):1-28.
    Justifying religious exemptions is a complicated matter. Citizens ask to not be subject to laws that everyone else must follow, raising worries about equal treatment. They ask to be exempted on a religious basis, a basis that secular citizens do not share, raising worries about the equal treatment of secular and religious citizens. And they ask governmental structures to create exceptions in the government’s own laws, raising worries about procedural fairness and stability. We nonetheless think some religious exemptions (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  32.  6
    Vaccine Exemptions and the Church-State Problem.Dena S. Davis - 2017 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 28 (3):250-254.
    All of the 50 states of the United States have laws governing childhood vaccinations; 48 allow for religious exemptions, while 19 also offer exemptions based on some sort of personal philosophy. Recent disease outbreaks have caused these states to reconsider philosophical exemptions. However, we cannot, consistent with the U.S. Constitution, give preference to religion by creating religious exemptions only. The Constitution requires states to put religious and nonreligious claims on equal footing. Given the ubiquity of nonreligious (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  15
    " Exempt" research after the privacy rule.Mark Barnes & Katherine E. Gallin - 2002 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 25 (4):5-6.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  20
    Exemptions to the Law, Freedom of Religion and Freedom of Conscience in Postsecular Societies.François Boucher - 2013 - Philosophy and Public Issues - Filosofia E Questioni Pubbliche 3 (2).
  35.  17
    Frontières de la liberté religieuse et exemptions individuelles.Saaz Taher - 2019 - ThéoRèmes 15 (15).
    In the last chapter of her book Liberalism's Religion [2017], Cécile Laborde argues that it is the practices and beliefs aimed at protecting individual integrity that can be candidates for exemptions. It therefore proposes two tests (sincerity and acceptability) in order to assess the link between these beliefs and practices and the individual’s integrity and considers the setting up of a deliberative process. We argue in this article that these two tests and the establishment of a deliberative process are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  5
    Tax-Exempt Status and Integrated Delivery Systems.Lisa C. Choi - 1995 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 23 (4):403-406.
    Within the health care industry, the move from regulatory cost controls to market competition has generated rapid and dramatic restructuring of providers. To enhance their competitive positions in the evolving market, many health care organizations are pursuing the ownership and integration of all elements and stages of health care delivery and payment, with the goal of increasing access to capital and lowering costs through administrative efficiencies and economies of scale. As of July 1994, 24 percent of hospitals were members of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  28
    Equipoise and Nonmedical Risks.Brandon Boesch - 2014 - American Journal of Bioethics 14 (4):16-18.
    DeMarco and colleagues present a compelling method of dealing with medical risks for which there is equipoise which might be implicated in a given research protocol. This commentary examines how the proposed model should inform the disclosure of other, non-medical risks. Since equipoise is a fairly unclear notion for non-medical risks (since there is little sense of professional uncertainty regarding these risks), this could lead to the inclusion of nearly unlimited non-medical risks. To account for these risks more reasonably, I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38.  34
    Exemptions From Influenza Vaccinations for Health Care Personnel Based on Self or Identity Issues: Are They Justified?David Trafimow - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (9):44-46.
  39.  13
    Exemption from the Torture Ban? A Moral Critique of the Bush Administration's Policy.Norman K. Swazo - 2007 - Public Affairs Quarterly 21 (1):61-87.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  14
    Commentary: Exemption from Review, Not Informed Consent.E. L. Pattullo - 1987 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 9 (5):6.
  41.  22
    Religious Exemptions to Equality.Hege Skjeie - 2007 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 10 (4):471-490.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  22
    Toleration, neutrality, and exemption.Peter Jones - 2020 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 23 (2):203-210.
    I focus on some controversial features of Peter Balint’s stimulating and provocative reassessment of the place of toleration in contemporary diverse societies. First, I question his argument that we must enlarge the concept of toleration to include indifference and approval if toleration is to be compatible with state neutrality. Secondly, I suggest that his idea of active neutrality of intent risks encountering the same difficulties as neutrality of outcome, although these will be mitigated the more the state’s neutrality takes a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  75
    The “Parental Love” Objection to Nonmedical Sex Selection: Deepening the Argument.Peter Herissone-Kelly - 2007 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 16 (4):446.
    In my paper “Parental Love and the Ethics of Sex Selection,” published in the previous issue of the Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, I set out to determine whether a plausible argument could be constructed in support of a common intuition about the ethics of sex selection. The intuition in question is that sex selection for nonmedical reasons is incompatible with a proper parental love: that is, with the sort of love that a parent ought to have for her (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44.  13
    Equal Treatment and Exemptions.Michael McGann - 2012 - Social Theory and Practice 38 (1):1-32.
    While supporters argue that exemptions are needed to equalize opportunities, critics claim they are unwarranted in principle and discriminatory in practice: equal treatment requires only facial neutrality whereas exemptions treat citizens unequally insofar as individuals with idiosyncratic commitments similarly burdened by general rules are rarely given an exemption.The upshot of this critique is that the burdens of cultural and religious commitments ought to be treated as expensive tastes. I argue that religious and cultural commitments cannot be reduced to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45. Mental Illness, Exemption & Moral Exclusion: the role of Interpretative Generosity.Anna Hartford & Dan J. Stein - forthcoming - Philosophical Explorations.
    Exemption from blameworthiness is often bound to implicit or explicit claims of diminished agency, or even non-agency. This poses a dilemma in navigating moral relationships affected by mental illness. While it is crucial for assessments of responsibility to be responsive to the significance of mental illness, must this responsiveness come at a cost to symmetrical moral relations? In this paper we argue, contra recent critiques, that Strawsonian accounts of responsibility are able to navigate this dilemma, and can accommodate significant exculpation (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  65
    The financial crisis, the exemption view and the problem of the harmless torturer.Michael Schefczyk - 2012 - Philosophy of Management 11 (1):2538.
    Richard Posner avers in his A Failure of Capitalism that managers bear no moral responsibility for the financial crisis. This view has numerous supporters in economics and philosophy, and I shall call it the ‘exemption view’. In this paper, I criticise four arguments for the exemption view and propose a superior alternative, the ‘participation view’. The participation view claims that managers can be co-responsible for harm, even if their actions were not necessary or sufficient conditions for its occurrence. The paper (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Excuses, Exemptions, and the Challenges to Social Naturalism.Sybren Heyndels - 2022 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 30 (1):72-85.
    Pamela Hieronymi has authored a very insightful book that focuses on one of the most influential articles in 20th century philosophy: P. F. Strawson’s ‘Freedom and Resentment’ (1962). Hieronymi’s principal objective in Freedom, Resentment, and the Metaphysics of Morals is to reconstruct and evaluate the central argumentative strategy in Strawson’s essay. The author’s aim is ‘to show that it can withstand the objections that are both the most obvious and the most serious, leaving it a worthy contender’ (3). In the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  20
    Does informed consent exempt Japanese doctors from reporting therapeutic deaths?H. Ikegaya - 2006 - Journal of Medical Ethics 32 (2):114-116.
    The Japanese Medical Act section 21 states that doctors must report unnatural deaths to the police, even though the term “unnatural death” is not defined by law. However, many doctors are reluctant to report potential therapeutic deaths . The Japanese Society of Legal Medicine has submitted guidelines for unnatural death, including PTD. These define a PTD as an unexpected death, the cause of which is unknown, but which is potentially related to medical practice. Such deaths are “reportable” to the coroner (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  20
    Should the Religious Be Exempt? Questions of Justice, Character, and the Maintenance of Norms.Laura S. Underkuffler - 2018 - Criminal Justice Ethics 37 (1):87-101.
    Religious exemptions present an anomaly in American law. Under the power of religious exemptions, individuals and organizations whose actions violate civil and criminal laws are exempt from those l...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  45
    The Exemption of Women from Labor.Lester F. Ward - 1894 - The Monist 4 (3):385-395.
1 — 50 / 857