Results for 'reasonable agreement'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Moral Objectivity and Reasonable Agreement: Can Realism Be Reconciled with Kantian Constructivism?Cristina Lafont - 2004 - Ratio Juris 17 (1):27-51.
    In this paper I analyze the tension between realism and antirealism at the basis of Kantian constructivism. This tension generates a conflictive account of the source of the validity of social norms. On the one hand, the claim to moral objectivity characteristic of Kantian moral theories makes the validity of norms depend on realist assumptions concerning the existence of shared fundamental interests among all rational human beings. I illustrate this claim through a comparison of the approaches of Rawls, Habermas and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  2.  29
    Reasoned agreement versus practical reasonableness: Grounding human rights in Maritain and Rawls.Meghan J. Clark - 2012 - Heythrop Journal 53 (4):637-648.
  3.  20
    Justice, Democracy and Reasonable Agreement, by Colin Farrelly.S. Birnbaum - 2009 - Mind 118 (471):827-830.
  4. Normal measurement and reasonable agreement.T. S. Kuhn - 1982 - In Barry Barnes & David O. Edge (eds.), Science in Context: Readings in the Sociology of Science. MIT Press. pp. 75--93.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. Neutrality, Toleration and Reasonable Agreement.Colin Farrelly - unknown
    It is widely agreed, claims John Horton, “that the core of the concept of toleration is the refusal, where one has the power to do so, to prohibit or seriously interfere with conduct one finds objectionable”.1 Liberals champion toleration as one of the main political virtues of a just society. The tolerant society is one which protects a diverse array of fundamental freedoms ranging from freedom of conscience and religion to freedom of expression and freedom of association. Secure in the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. Justice, Democracy and Reasonable Agreement[REVIEW]Gabriel Wollner - 2010 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 7 (2):294-296.
  7. Moral contractualism is a type of view in ethics that attempts to justify morality, or at least a part of it, by appealing to some sort of rational or reasonable agreement among individuals. 1 In What We Owe to Each Other, TM Scanlon defends a contractualist account of that part of morality that concerns our obligations to.Mark Timmons - 2004 - In Philip Stratton-Lake (ed.), On What We Owe to Each Other. Blackwell. pp. 90.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  16
    Reasons for Agreeing, Reasons for Complying: The Paris Agreement and the Compliance Issue.Silvia Bacchetta - 2020 - Rivista di Estetica 75:72-83.
    How should we deal with noncompliance in the context of the Paris Agreement? After having delimited the scope of noncompliance as a motivational issue, I will argue that two kinds of reasons can motivate agents to comply, moral and prudential reasons. Then, I will show that moral and prudential reasons can motivate compliance, although in different ways, as moral reasons require the institutions, whereas prudential reasons are thought to be self-sufficing. Prudential reasons come with the assumption that they have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  71
    Agreements, undertakings, and practical reason.Oliver Black - 2004 - Legal Theory 10 (2):77-95.
    This paper argues for two models of agreement which develop the idea that there is an agreement where one party gives a conditional undertaking and the other responds with an unconditional undertaking. The models accommodate plausible justifications for making and complying with agreements.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  58
    Reasoned Moral Agreement: Applying Discourse Ethics within Organizations.Jason Stansbury - 2009 - Business Ethics Quarterly 19 (1):33-56.
    ABSTRACT:Whether at the executive or the line-management levels, businesspeople face moral decisions that cannot be easily resolved with reference to a shared ethos, whether because of diversity of ethea in the organization or its environment, or because the organization's ethos is inadequate for the problem at hand. These decisions are made more common by the changing norms of a pluralistic business environment, and require collective moral deliberation to be adequately resolved. Discourse ethics ideally characterizes the form of valid collective moral (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  11. Reason and agreement in social contract views.Samuel Freeman - 1990 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (2):122-157.
  12.  23
    Investigating cognitive moral reasoning: The effect of dilemma context and gender agreement between the subject and the dilemma actor.James Weber & Dina Nasri Siniora - 2021 - Business and Society Review 126 (4):455-478.
    Our research extends the current understanding of cognitive moral reasoning research by considering the often‐overlooked element of context, specifically the issue presented in the ethical dilemma, and the issue of gender agreement between the subject and the dilemma actor. We rely on gender identity and cognitive moral reasoning theories to provide the theoretical underpinnings of our exploration to deepen our understanding of the contextual forces affecting cognitive moral reasoning. Our results generally confirm earlier research findings and provide valuable information (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13. Reason, attitude, and knowledge as predictors of assertion agreement.Jf Voss, R. Finchelkiefer & L. Ney - 1987 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 25 (5):325-325.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  6
    Contract law, economic reasoning, and trade agreements.Elise Vâlcu - 2008 - Linguistic and Philosophical Investigations 7.
  15.  74
    Agreement Theorems in Dynamic-Epistemic Logic.Cédric Dégremont & Oliver Roy - 2012 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 41 (4):735-764.
    This paper introduces Agreement Theorems to dynamic-epistemic logic. We show first that common belief of posteriors is sufficient for agreement in epistemic-plausibility models, under common and well-founded priors. We do not restrict ourselves to the finite case, showing that in countable structures the results hold if and only if the underlying plausibility ordering is well-founded. We then show that neither well-foundedness nor common priors are expressible in the language commonly used to describe and reason about epistemic-plausibility models. The (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  16. Agreements, coercion, and obligation.Margaret Gilbert - 1993 - Ethics 103 (4):679-706.
    Typical agreements can be seen as joint decisions, inherently involving obligations of a distinctive kind. These obligations derive from the joint commitment' that underlies a joint decision. One consequence of this understanding of agreements and their obligations is that coerced agreements are possible and impose obligations. It is not that the parties to an agreement should always conform to it, all things considered. Unless one is released from the agreement, however, one has some reason to conform to it, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  17. Philosophical Agreement and Philosophical Progress.Julia Smith - 2024 - Episteme:1-19.
    In the literature on philosophical progress it is often assumed that agreement is a necessary condition for progress. This assumption is sensible only if agreement is a reliable sign of the truth, since agreement on false answers to philosophical questions would not constitute progress. This paper asks whether agreement among philosophers is (or would be) likely to be a reliable sign of truth. Insights from social choice theory are used to identify the conditions under which (...) among philosophers would be a reliable indicator of the truth, and it is argued that we lack good reason to think that philosophical inquiry meets these conditions. The upshot is that philosophical agreement is epistemically uninformative: agreement on the answer to a philosophical question does not supply even a prima facie reason to think that the agreed-upon view is true. However, the epistemic uninformativeness of philosophical agreement is not an indictment of philosophy's progress, because philosophy is valuable independent of its ability to generate agreement on the correct answers to philosophical questions. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Agreement Matters: Critical Notice of Derek Parfit, On What Matters.Stephen Darwall - 2014 - Philosophical Review 123 (1):79-105.
    Derek Parfit's Reasons and Persons (1984) mounted a striking defense of Act Consequentialism against a Rawls-inspired Kantian orthodoxy in moral philosophy. On What Matters (2011) is notable for its serious engagement with Kant's ethics and for its arguments in support of the “Triple Theory,” which allies Rule Consequentialism with Kantian and Scanlonian Contractualism against Act Consequentialism as a theory of moral right. This critical notice argues that what underlies this change is a view of the deontic concept of moral rightness (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  19.  44
    Why Moral Agreement is Not Enough to Address Algorithmic Structural Bias.P. Benton - 2022 - Communications in Computer and Information Science 1551:323-334.
    One of the predominant debates in AI Ethics is the worry and necessity to create fair, transparent and accountable algorithms that do not perpetuate current social inequities. I offer a critical analysis of Reuben Binns’s argument in which he suggests using public reason to address the potential bias of the outcomes of machine learning algorithms. In contrast to him, I argue that ultimately what is needed is not public reason per se, but an audit of the implicit moral assumptions of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  21
    Verbal Agreements and the Pressure of Instability against the Convergence Conception of Political Liberalism.Saranga Sudarshan - 2023 - Journal of Social and Political Philosophy 2 (2):158-174.
    Political liberalism, or public reason liberalism, has taken a decisive turn towards the Convergence Conception of public justification and away from the orthodox Consensus Conception. Convergence theorists argue that public justification should be understood as all reasonable people having some conclusive reason to endorse coercively enforced moral rules that are issue and context specific. They argue for this on the basis that, given the nature of deep moral and political disagreement, only the Convergence Conception can show reasonable people (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  27
    The Legal Form of the Durban Platform Agreement: Seven Reasons for a Protocol.Christina Voigt - 2012 - Ethics, Policy and Environment 15 (3):276 - 282.
    Decision 1/cp.17 limits the choice of legal form of a new climate agreement to three options: a protocol, another legal instrument or an agreed outcome with legal force under the Climate Convention. This commentary provides seven reasons for the conclusion that a protocol is the only viable legal option to serve the object and purpose of the convention. The reasons include, inter alia, the exclusion of non-binding, soft law under a ‘result based regime’, multilateralism, a 5 year timeline which (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Morals by agreement.David P. Gauthier - 1986 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Is morality rational? In this book Gauthier argues that moral principles are principles of rational choice. He proposes a principle whereby choice is made on an agreed basis of cooperation, rather than according to what would give an individual the greatest expectation of value. He shows that such a principle not only ensures mutual benefit and fairness, thus satisfying the standards of morality, but also that each person may actually expect greater utility by adhering to morality, even though the choice (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   649 citations  
  23.  66
    Moral Dealing: Contract, Ethics, and Reason.Contractarianism and Rational Choice: Essays on David Gauthier's Morals by Agreement.David Gauthier - 1993 - Philosophical Quarterly 43 (172):373-378.
  24.  21
    Agreement Builds and Disagreement Destroys:” How Polish Undergraduates and Graduates Understand Interpersonal Arguing.Kamila Dębowska-Kozłowska & Dale Hample - 2022 - Argumentation 36 (3):365-392.
    This is a descriptive study (_N_ = 243) of how Polish undergraduates and graduates perceive face to face arguing. We had some reasons to suppose that they would not be especially aggressive. The Polish culture has a number of proverbs warning against combative arguing, with “agreement builds and disagreement destroys” being illustrative. In addition, up until 1989 public dissent and open disagreements were suppressed by the government, and older generations often found it prudent to avoid arguing. We compared Polish (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  8
    Agreements: a philosophical and legal study.Oliver Black - 2012 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Promises -- Offer and acceptance -- Obligation -- Practical reason -- Intention and other topics -- Intervention by the state -- Contract -- Competition -- Conspiracy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics.James Bohman & William Rehg (eds.) - 1997 - MIT Press.
    The contributions in this anthology address tensions that arise between reason and politics in a democracy inspired by the ideal of achieving reasoned agreement among free and equal citizens.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  27.  16
    Moral reasoning.R. W. Beardsmore - 1969 - New York,: Schocken Books.
    Accounts of moral reasoning have tended either to ignore the differences in what men count as good reasons for their moral judgments, or, in emphasizing these differences, to imply that anything whatsoever can count as a moral reason. This book shows that both of these positions rest on a mistaken assumption, and by rejecting this assumption brings out important features of moral discourse. Although moral disagreement is seen to be far more radical than empirical disagreement, a framework of agreement (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28. Extensive Philosophical Agreement and Progress.Bryan Frances - 2017 - Metaphilosophy 48 (1-2):47-57.
    This article argues, first, that there is plenty of agreement among philosophers on philosophically substantive claims, which fall into three categories: reasons for or against certain views, elementary truths regarding fundamental notions, and highly conditionalized claims. This agreement suggests that there is important philosophical progress. It then argues that although it's easy to list several potential kinds of philosophical progress, it is much harder to determine whether the potential is actual. Then the article attempts to articulate the truth (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  29. What is (Dis)Agreement?Darrell Patrick Rowbottom - 2018 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 97 (1):223-236.
    When do we agree? The answer might once have seemed simple and obvious; we agree that p when we each believe that p. But from a formal epistemological perspective, where degrees of belief are more fundamental than beliefs, this answer is unsatisfactory. On the one hand, there is reason to suppose that it is false; degrees of belief about p might differ when beliefs simpliciter on p do not. On the other hand, even if it is true, it is too (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  30.  24
    Promise, Agreement, Contract.Gregory Klass - forthcoming - In Hanoch Dagan & Benjamin Zipursky (eds.), Research Handbook on Private Law Theories.
    It is natural to wonder about contract law’s relationship to the morality of promises and agreements. This Chapter distinguishes two ways to conceive of that relationship. First, parties’ agreement-based moral obligations might figure into the explanation of contract law—into an account of its functions or justifications. Contract law might serve to enforce parties’ first-order performance obligations, to enforce second-order remedial obligations, to support the culture of making and keeping agreements more generally, or at least to do no harm to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  58
    The agreement to keep our agreements: Hume, Prichard, and Searle.Jan Narveson - 1994 - Philosophical Papers 23 (2):75-87.
    Does it make sense, and is it at all plausible, to view the moral obligation to keep particular promises and do what is called for by particular agreements such as contracts as being founded on a general "Social Contract" -- i.e., to give a contractarian account of promise-keeping? This paper argues that it does. Borrowing from Hume, David Lewis, Gilbert Harman, and David Gauthier, I provide a sketch of what the "social contract" is (not, e.g., either a real or a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  23
    Finding Agreement Among Environmentalists.Jack Weir - 2014 - Philosophy in the Contemporary World 21 (1):65-76.
    This article attempts to find grounds for agreement and tolerance among environmentalists, as well as all persons of good will who are reasonable and scientifically informed. It beguis by taking stock of where we are today in ethics in general, and then hi environmental ethics in particular. What are the major theories, their central ideas, and problems? Is there a way forward? Explained and defended throughout is the thesis that moral pluralism is the best way forward.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Incompatibility Semantics from Agreement.Daniele Porello - 2012 - Philosophia 40 (1):99-119.
    In this paper, I discuss the analysis of logic in the pragmatic approach recently proposed by Brandom. I consider different consequence relations, formalized by classical, intuitionistic and linear logic, and I will argue that the formal theory developed by Brandom, even if provides powerful foundational insights on the relationship between logic and discursive practices, cannot account for important reasoning patterns represented by non-monotonic or resource-sensitive inferences. Then, I will present an incompatibility semantics in the framework of linear logic which allow (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34. The anti-counterfeiting trade agreement: the ethical analysis of a failure, and its lessons.Luciano Floridi - 2015 - Ethics and Information Technology 17 (2):165-173.
    The anti-counterfeiting trade agreement was originally meant to harmonise and enforce intellectual property rights provisions in existing trade agreements within a wider group of countries. This was commendable in itself, so ACTA’s failure was all the more disappointing. In this article, I wish to contribute to the post-ACTA debate by proposing a specific analysis of the ethical reasons why ACTA failed, and what we can learn from them. I argue that five kinds of objections—namely, secret negotiations, lack of consultation, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  54
    Desires, Reasons, and Causes.Stephen Darwall - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (2):436-443.
    Jonathan Dancy’s Practical Reality makes a significant contribution to clarifying the relationship between desire and reasons for acting, both the normative reasons we seek in deliberation and the motivating reasons we cite in explanation. About the former, Dancy argues that, not only are normative reasons not all grounded in desires, but, more radically, the fact that one desires something is never itself a normative reason. And he argues that desires fail to figure in motivating reasons also, concluding that neither the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  36.  45
    Living in Agreement with a Contract: The Management of Moral and Viable Firm–Stakeholder Relationships.Kalle Pajunen - 2006 - Journal of Business Ethics 68 (3):243-258.
    In a contractual firm–stakeholder relationship the participants are expected to act according to the agreement and for mutual benefit. By acting against the agreement at the expense of the other participant, however, may result in higher individual profits within a short period of time. Building on the unlocked iterated prisoner’s dilemma (PD) setting, Scanlon’s [Scanlon, T.␣M.: 1998, What We Owe to Each Other (Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass)] version of contractualism, and the social dilemma literature, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  37. Reason in its Practical Application.E. Sonny Elizondo - 2013 - Philosophers' Imprint 13:1-17.
    Is practical reason a cognitive faculty? Do practical judgments make claims about a subject matter that are appropriately assessed in terms of their agreement with that subject matter? According to Kantians like Christine Korsgaard, the answer is no. To think otherwise is to conflate the theoretical and the practical, the epistemic and the ethical. I am not convinced. In this paper, I motivate my skepticism through examination of the very figure who inspires Korsgaard’s rejection of cognitivism: Kant. For as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  38. Sexual Consent as Voluntary Agreement: Tales of “Seduction” or Questions of Law?Lucinda Vandervort - 2013 - New Criminal Law Review 16 (1):143-201.
    This article proposes a rigorous method to “map” the law on to the facts in the legal analysis of “sexual consent” using a series of mandatory questions of law designed to eliminate the legal errors often made by decision-makers who routinely rely on personal beliefs about and attitudes towards “normal sexual behavior” in screening and deciding cases. In Canada, sexual consent is affirmative consent, the communication by words or conduct of “voluntary agreement” to a specific sexual activity, with a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  33
    Deferred Prosecution Agreements and the Presumption of Innocence.Roger A. Shiner & Henry Ho - 2018 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 12 (4):707-723.
    A deferred prosecution agreement, or DPA, allows a corporation, instead of proceeding to trial on a criminal charge, to settle matters with the state by acknowledging the facts on which any charge would be based, pay a reduced fine, and agree to change the way they conduct business. Critics of DPAs have suggested that, because the defendant corporation must pay a fine and submit to structural reform without having been found guilty at trial, DPAs violate the Presumption of Innocence. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  58
    Being reasonable in the face of pluralism and other alleged problems for Global Justice: a reply to van Hooft.Gillian Brock - 2010 - Ethics and Global Politics 3 (2):155-170.
    In his recent review essay, Stan van Hooft raises some interesting potential challenges for cosmopolitan global justice projects, of which my version is one example.1 I am grateful to van Hooft for doing so. I hope by responding to these challenges here, others concerned with developing frameworks for analyzing issues of global justice will also learn something of value. I start by giving a very brief synopsis of key themes of my book, Global Justice,2 so I can address van Hooft’s (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  45
    Are coerced agreements involuntary?Michael Philips - 1984 - Law and Philosophy 3 (1):133 - 145.
    It is widely supposed that agreements made in response to coercion are entered into involuntarily for that reason. This paper argues that that supposition is false and that it has generated a good deal of avoidable confusion in the courts and among some legal commentators. Agreements entered into involuntarily of course, have no legal standing. But, on any plausible account of coercion, agreements entered into in response to coercion are an inevitability of social life. To prohibit them would be to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  22
    Constitutional reason and political identity.Shane O'Neill - 2001 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 4 (3):1-26.
    This article presents a normative‐theoretical account of democratic legitimacy that meets the challenge of moral and cultural pluralism in a way that takes the avoidance of oppression and violence to be a fundamental imperative. The discourse‐theoretical perspective of jürgen Habermas reveals that reasoned agreement among citizens is the only alternative to political oppression. Pace Habermas, however, the legitimacy of even basic constitutional principles does not require us to agree with one another for the same reasons. While we can affirm (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  21
    Principles of Public Reason in the UNFCCC: Rethinking the Equity Framework.Idil Boran - 2017 - Science and Engineering Ethics 23 (5):1253-1271.
    Since 2011, the focus of international negotiations under the UNFCCC has been on producing a new climate agreement to be adopted in 2015. This phase of negotiations is known as the Durban Platform for Enhanced Action. The goal has been to update the global effort on climate for long-term cooperation. In this period, various changes have been contemplated on the design of the architecture of the global climate effort. Whereas previously, the negotiation process consisted of setting mandated targets exclusively (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  21
    Eastern Orthodox Agreement and Disagreement with Kenneth Collins and Jerry Walls.Gary Hartenburg - 2020 - Perichoresis 18 (5):39-54.
    In their book, Roman but Not Catholic, Kenneth Collins and Jerry Walls make the case that certain beliefs central to the Roman Catholic faith are unreasonable. This article evaluates, from the point of view of Eastern Orthodoxy, some of the arguments Collins and Walls make. In particular, it argues first that Collins and Walls are correct to criticize John Henry Newman’s theory of the development of doctrine as a reason to accept otherwise insufficiently supported Catholic doctrines. Secondly, it offers some (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  69
    Science as Public Reason: A Restatement.Cristóbal Bellolio Badiola - 2018 - Res Publica 24 (4):415-432.
    According to John Rawls, the methods and conclusions of science—when these are non-controversial—constitute public reasons. However, several objections have been raised against this view. This paper focuses on two objections. On the one hand, the associational objection states that scientific reasons are the reasons of the scientific community, and thus paradigmatically non-public in the Rawlsian sense. On the other hand, the controversiality objection states that the non-controversiality requirement rules out their public character when scientific postulates are resisted by a significant (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  46.  5
    Gaining control? bilateral labor agreements and the shared interest of sending and receiving countries to control migrant workers and the illicit migration industry.Hila Shamir & Yuval Livnat - 2022 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 23 (2):65-94.
    Countries increasingly have been entering bilateral labor agreements as a tool for the regulation and governance of short-term temporary labor migration worldwide. However, these are often confidential legal instruments, and consequently we know relatively little about their actual content and impact, and why countries choose to enter them. This Article complements existing explanations in the literature regarding the reasons why countries enter BLAs and their potential to create and improve migrant workers’ rights. Based on a detailed content analysis of 81 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. When is consensus knowledge based? Distinguishing shared knowledge from mere agreement.Boaz Miller - 2013 - Synthese 190 (7):1293-1316.
    Scientific consensus is widely deferred to in public debates as a social indicator of the existence of knowledge. However, it is far from clear that such deference to consensus is always justified. The existence of agreement in a community of researchers is a contingent fact, and researchers may reach a consensus for all kinds of reasons, such as fighting a common foe or sharing a common bias. Scientific consensus, by itself, does not necessarily indicate the existence of shared knowledge (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  48.  16
    What reasons do those with practical experience use in deciding on priorities for healthcare resources? A qualitative study.A. Hasman, E. Mcintosh & T. Hope - 2008 - Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (9):658-663.
    Background: Priority setting is necessary in current healthcare services. Discussion of fair process has highlighted the value of developing reasons for allocation decisions on the basis of experience gained from real cases.Aim: To identify the reasons that those with experience of real decision-making concerning resource allocation think relevant in deciding on the priority of a new but expensive drug treatment.Methods: Semistructured interviews with members of committees with responsibility for making resource allocation decisions at a local level in the British National (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  32
    Reasoning Together: Temptations, Dangers, and Cautions.Chris Campolo & Dale Turner - 2002 - Argumentation 16 (1):3-19.
    In the appropriate contexts reasoning is a powerful tool for producing intersubjective agreement about what counts as the best answer to a question that generates inquiry; sometimes employing arguments can lead to agreement about what is the right answer. In this paper we hope to show, however, that unabashed optimism about the power of argument is misplaced. Such optimism rests on an implausible picture of the power of articulation. Sentences cashed out as reasons to believe another sentence is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  50.  21
    Problems of Liability for Breach of a Preliminary Agreement.Dangutė Ambrasienė & Indrė Kryžiūtė - 2012 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 19 (2):561-583.
    Due to its specificity, the legal institute of preliminary agreement poses a number of questions. This pre-contractual agreement is not yet a contract. Therefore, the form and scope of legal protection will not be the same as that guaranteed to contracting parties. However, the European legal systems would claim that the relationships between the parties during pre-contractual negotiations have to be regulated and protected by the law. The first part of this article deals with the legal nature of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000