Switch to: References

Citations of:

Hegel's science of logic

Amherst, N.Y.: Humanity Books (1929)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Anonymity, Responsibility, and the Many Faces of Capitalism.Ardis B. Collins - 2015 - In Andrew Buchwalter (ed.), Hegel and Capitalism. Albany: State University of New York Press. pp. 53-69.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hegel and Capitalism.Andrew Buchwalter (ed.) - 2015 - Albany: State University of New York Press.
    Examines Hegel’s unique understanding and assessment of capitalism as an economic, social, and cultural phenomenon.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Action: Offshoring Strategies, Creative Governance, and Subnational Island Jurisdictions.Rowland Stout - 2006 - McGill-Queen's University Press.
    By focusing on the idea that agency involves causal sensitivity to reasons, Rowland Stout shows how agency is one of the most useful ways into the philosophy of mind: if one can understand what it is to be a free and rational agent, then one can understand what it is to be a conscious subject of experience. Some of the questions considered include: Is all action intentional action? Is intentional action characterized by its relation with possible justification? Do beliefs motivate (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • CRITIQUE OF IMPURE REASON: Horizons of Possibility and Meaning.Steven James Bartlett - 2021 - Salem, USA: Studies in Theory and Behavior.
    PLEASE NOTE: This is the corrected 2nd eBook edition, 2021. ●●●●● _Critique of Impure Reason_ has now also been published in a printed edition. To reduce the otherwise high price of this scholarly, technical book of nearly 900 pages and make it more widely available beyond university libraries to individual readers, the non-profit publisher and the author have agreed to issue the printed edition at cost. ●●●●● The printed edition was released on September 1, 2021 and is now available through (...)
    Direct download (15 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Essential Difference: Toward a Metaphysics of Emergence.James Blachowicz - 2012 - State University of New York Press.
    Proposes a new way of understanding the nature of metaphysics, focusing on nonreductionist emergence theory, both in ancient and modern philosophy, as well as in contemporary philosophy of science.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Understanding dialectical thinking from a cultural-historical perspective.Wan-chi Wong - 2006 - Philosophical Psychology 19 (2):239 – 260.
    The present essay aims to throw light on the study of dialectical thinking from a cultural-historical perspective. Different forms of dialectic are articulated as ideal types, including the Greek dialectic, the Hegelian dialectic, the contemporary German negative dialectic, the Chinese dialectic, and the Indian negative dialectic. These influential cultural products in the history of the East and the West, articulated as ideal types, serve as constellations that could facilitate further empirical studies on dialectical thinking. An understanding of the complexity of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Religious Experience as Self-Transcendance and Self-Deception.Merold Westphal - 1992 - Faith and Philosophy 9 (2):168-192.
  • The problem of change.Ryan Wasserman - 2006 - Philosophy Compass 1 (1):48–57.
    Our world is a world of change. Children are born and grow into adults. Material possessions rust and decay with age and ultimately perish. Yet scepticism about change is as old as philosophy itself. Heraclitus, for example, argued that nothing could survive the replacement of parts, so that it is impossible to step into the same river twice. Zeno argued that motion is paradoxical, so that nothing can alter its location. Parmenides and his followers went even further, arguing that the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The Unnameable.Alasdair Urquhart - 2008 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (S1):119-135.
    Hans Herzberger as a philosopher and logician has shown deep interest both in the philosophy of Gottlob Frege, and in the topic of the inexpressible and the ineffable. In the fall of 1982, he taught at the University of Toronto, together with André Gombay, a course on Frege's metaphysics, philosophy of language, and foundations of arithmetic. Again, in the fall of 1986, he taught a seminar on the philosophy of language that dealt with 'the limits of discursive symbolism in several (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The primary process of groups, its systematics and representation.Guy E. Swanson - 1974 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 4 (1):53–69.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • British Hegelianism: A Non‐Metaphysical View?Robert Stern - 1994 - European Journal of Philosophy 2 (3):293-321.
    This article puts forward a revisionary reading of Hegel's reception in Britain at the turn of the nineteenth century, in suggesting that the stance of the British Hegelians is very close to the sort of non-metaphysical or category theory interpretations that have been in vogue amongst contemporary commentators. It is shown that the British Hegelians arrived at this position as a way of responding to the hostile existentialist reaction to Hegel begun by Schelling in the 1840s, which led them to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hegel and Deleuze on the metaphysical interpretation of the calculus.Henry Somers-Hall - 2009 - Continental Philosophy Review 42 (4):555-572.
    The aim of this paper is to explore the uses made of the calculus by Gilles Deleuze and G. W. F. Hegel. I show how both Deleuze and Hegel see the calculus as providing a way of thinking outside of finite representation. For Hegel, this involves attempting to show that the foundations of the calculus cannot be thought by the finite understanding, and necessitate a move to the standpoint of infinite reason. I analyse Hegel’s justification for this introduction of dialectical (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Hegel and Peircean abduction.Paul Redding - 2003 - European Journal of Philosophy 11 (3):295–313.
  • Hegel’s Relational Organicism: The Mediation of Individualism and Holism.Philip A. Quadrio - 2012 - Critical Horizons 13 (3):317 - 336.
    This paper is concerned with organic conceptions of socio-political life and is concerned with the rehabilitation of organicism as a positive social ontology. It demonstrates that: organicism does not necessarily imply the negation of individuality by a monolithic society, and; that G. W. F. Hegel’s references to the state as organic do not imply social holism. With Hegel’s organicism, as with Idealist organicism generally, what is found is a relational rather than a holistic social ontology. This relational ontology is one (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Brandom's Hegel.Robert B. Pippin - 2005 - European Journal of Philosophy 13 (3):381–408.
  • Hegel’s spirit, Marxist aesthetics and Stalinist restoration: the tragic philosophy of history of Mikhail Lifshits.Vesa Oittinen - 2016 - Studies in East European Thought 68 (4):331-342.
    The article focuses on one highly idiosyncratic trait of Lifshits’ reading of Hegel, namely his assertion that the epoch of Restoration during which Hegel produced his main works was analogous to the period of the 1930s in the USSR. In both cases, “constructive” tasks came to the fore as the fermentation of the revolutionary era waned. On this assumption, Lifshits built up his idea of a Restauratio magna, which should serve as the guiding star of cultural politics. In fact, Lifshits (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hegel and the Sway of the Negative – By Karin de Boer. [REVIEW]Andrew Norris - 2013 - European Journal of Philosophy 21 (S3):e5-e10.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hegel’s Idealist Reading of Spinoza.Samuel Newlands - 2011 - Philosophy Compass 6 (2):100-108.
    In this two-part series, I explore some of the most important and influential interpretations of Spinoza as an idealist. In this first part, I examine Hegel’s case for interpreting Spinoza as a kind of frustrated idealist and show how doing so raises fresh interpretative challenges for Spinoza’s contemporary readers.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Opposites, Contradictories, and Mediation in Kierkegaard's Critique of Hegel.Shannon Nason - 2011 - Heythrop Journal 52 (6):24-36.
    In this paper I argue that Kierkegaard endorses Hegel's theory of mediation, the view that relative opposites are mediated. However, I show that Kierkegaard denies Hegel's thesis that there are all and only relative opposites. I develop two of his arguments against this thesis. The first is existential. This argument comes from the dramatic interplay between A, the often disagreeable aesthete of Either/Or I, and Judge William, the dutiful ethicist of Either/Or II. Judge William convincingly argues that the possibility of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Grammatical Background of Kant's General Logic.Kurt Mosser - 2008 - Kantian Review 13 (1):116-140.
    In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant conceives of general logic as a set of universal and necessary rules for the possibility of thought, or as a set of minimal necessary conditions for ascribing rationality to an agent . Such a conception, of course, contrasts with contemporary notions of formal, mathematical or symbolic logic. Yet, in so far as Kant seeks to identify those conditions that must hold for the possibility of thought in general, such conditions must hold a fortiori (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hegel's theory of freedom.Craig Matarrese - 2007 - Philosophy Compass 2 (2):170–186.
    Hegel’s theory of freedom is complex and sweeping, and while most interpreters of Hegel will readily agree that it is the centerpiece of his political philosophy, perhaps also of his social philosophy and philosophy of history, they will just as readily disagree about what exactly the theory claims. Such interpretive disagreements have fueled, in large part, the resurgence of interest in Hegelian philosophy over the last few decades.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Providence and Pantheism.W. J. Mander - 2022 - Sophia 61 (3):599-609.
    This paper argues that a strong thesis of divine providence, whereby God is understood as in complete control of all things, entails pantheism, the thesis that the universe is not ontologically distinct from God. In normal discourse, we distinguish a plan from, on the one hand, the state of affairs which realizes that plan—its execution or expression—and, on the other hand, the person or group whose plan it is. However, with respect to an omnipotent God who displays complete providence, neither (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the 'undialectical': normativity in Hegel.Iain Macdonald - 2011 - Continental Philosophy Review 45 (1):121-141.
    This paper addresses the question of normativity in Hegel by examining the role of ‘undialectical’ resistance to dialectical development. Beginning with a general overview of dialectical normativity and what it might mean to be ‘undialectical,’ the focus then shifts to a privileged example in Hegel’s writings: Sophocles’ Antigone. The central claim of the paper is the following: The very contradictions that fuel dialectical normativity can also trap individuals within an obsolete actuality, without immediate hope of escape. Indeed, the irreducible dependence (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The rise of the non-metaphysical Hegel.Simon Lumsden - 2008 - Philosophy Compass 3 (1):51–65.
    There has been a resurgence of interest in Hegel's thought by Anglo‐American philosophers in the last 25 years. That expansion of interest was initiated with the publication of Charles Taylor's Hegel (1975). That work stills stands as one of7 the important branches of Hegel interpretation. However the dominance of the strongly metaphysical interpretation of Hegel, which dominated the understanding of Hegel until the 1980s, and of which Taylor's work represents the culmination, has now, at least among the major interpreters of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Dignity at the Limit: Jean-Luc Nancy on the Possibility of Incommensurable Worth.Bryan Lueck - 2016 - Continental Philosophy Review 49 (3):309-323.
    Dignity, according to some recent arguments, is a useless concept, giving vague expression to moral intuitions that are better captured by other, better defined concepts. In this paper, I defend the concept of dignity against such skeptical arguments. I begin with a description of the defining features of the Kantian conception of dignity. I then examine one of the strongest arguments against that conception, advanced by Arthur Schopenhauer in On the Basis of Morality. After considering some standard accounts of dignity, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hegel's metaphysics: Changing the debate.James Kreines - 2006 - Philosophy Compass 1 (5):466–480.
    There are two general approaches to Hegel’s theoretical philosophy which are broadly popular in recent work. Debate between them is often characterized, by both sides, as a dispute between those favoring a more traditional “metaphysical” approach and those favoring a newer “nonmetaphysical” approach. But I argue that the most important and compelling points made by both sides are actually independent of the idea of a “nonmetaphysical” interpretation of Hegel, which is itself simply unconvincing. The most promising directions for future research, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • On negativity in Revolution in Poetic Language.Sina Kramer - 2013 - Continental Philosophy Review 46 (3):465-479.
    Kristeva’s Revolution in Poetic Language offers a challenge to theories of the subject in psychoanalysis, linguistic theory, and in philosophy. Central to that challenge is Kristeva’s conception of negativity. In this article, I trace the development of the concept of negativity in Revolution in Poetic Language from its root in Hegel, to rejection, which Kristeva develops out of Freud. Both are crucial to the development of the material dialectic between the semiotic and the symbolic that makes up Kristeva’s subject-in-process/on trial. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When seeing is not believing: A critique of Priest's argument from perception.Paul Kabay - 2006 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (3):443 – 460.
    In this paper I critically examine an argument proposed by Graham Priest in support of the claim that the observable world is consistent. According to this argument we have good reason to think that the observable world is consistent, specifically we perceive it to be consistent. I critique this argument on two fronts. First, Priest appears to reason from the claim 'we know what it is to have a contradictory perception' to the claim 'we know what it is to perceive (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hegelians Axel Honneth and Robert Williams on the Development of Human Morality.Rauno Huttunen - 2011 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 31 (4):339-355.
    An individual is in the lowest phase of moral development if he thinks only of his own personal interest and has only his own selfish agenda in his mind as he encounters other humans. This lowest phase corresponds well with sixteenth century British moral egoism which reflects the rise of the new economic order. Adam Smith (1723–1790) wanted to defend this new economic order which is based on economic exchange between egoistic individuals. Nevertheless, he surely did not want to support (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Thought and experience in Hegel and McDowell.Stephen Houlgate - 2006 - European Journal of Philosophy 14 (2):242–261.
  • Hegelian Restorative Justice.Brandon Hogan - 2023 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 61 (1):82-111.
    In the Philosophy of Right, Hegel claims that crime is a negation of right and punishment is the “negation of the negation.” Punishment, for Hegel, “annuls” the criminal act. Many take it that Hegel endorses a form of retributivism—the theory that criminal offenders should be subject to harsh treatment in response and in proportion to their wrongdoing. Here I argue that restorative criminal justice is consistent with Hegel's remarks on punishment and his overall philosophical system. This is true, in part, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Grammar of the Human Life Process: John Dewey's new theory of language.Fred Harris - 2012 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 44 (s1):18-30.
    Dewey proposed a new theory of language, in which the form (such as symbols) and content of language are not separated. The content of language includes the physical aspects of the world, which are purely quantitative: the life process, which involves functional responses to qualities, and the human life process, which involves the conscious integration of the potentiality of qualities to form a functional whole. The pinnacle of this process is individuality, or the emergence of a unique function to change (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A globalist ideology of post‐Marxism? Hardt and Negri's Empire.Gary K. Browning - 2005 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 8 (2):193-208.
    Hardt and Negri interpret contemporary sovereignty and politics in the light of a theory of contemporary globalization that is taken to supersede Marxism and former ideological standpoints of the Left. In particular, Hardt and Negri highlight how their reading of empire and multitude breaks with the teleology of Marxism and accepts the openness of events. They advertise the novelty, which is held to consist in their recognition of a thoroughly socialized and globalized world in which there exists no predetermined historical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Form of Truth: Hegel’s Philosophical Logic: by E. Ficara, Berlin, Boston, de Gruyter, 2021, 226+11 pp., €109.95, ISBN: 9783110703658.J. E. Maybee - 2021 - History and Philosophy of Logic 43 (2):201-206.
    In The Form of Truth: Hegel’s Philosophical Logic, Elena Ficara offers a reappraisal of G.W.F. Hegel’s logic within the history of logic and in relation to the logics of today. She brings together...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Against universal mereological composition.Crawford Elder - 2008 - Dialectica 62 (4):433-454.
    This paper opposes universal mereological composition (UMC). Sider defends it: unless UMC were true, he says, it could be indeterminate how many objects there are in the world. I argue that there is no general connection between how widely composition occurs and how many objects there are in the world. Sider fails to support UMC. I further argue that we should disbelieve in UMC objects. Existing objections against them say that they are radically unlike Aristotelian substances. True, but there is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • A pantheist in spite of himself: Craig, Hegel, and divine infinity.Russell W. Dumke - 2016 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 80 (3):243-257.
    In his 2006 paper `Pantheists in Spite of Themselves: God and Infinity in Contemporary Theology,’ William Lane Craig examines the work of Wolfhart Pannenberg, Philip Clayton, and F. LeRon Shults, whose conceptions of God are influenced by Hegel. Craig shows that these thinkers’ Hegelian formulations lead to monism, despite their attempts to avoid it. He then attempts to refute Hegelian thinking by appealing to Cantor. I argue that that this refutation fails because Cantor and Hegel are far more amicable than (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze’s Critical Engagement with Hegel.Simon Duffy - 2009 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 17 (4):563 – 582.
    The role of mathematics in the development of Gilles Deleuze's (1925-95) philosophy of difference as an alternative to the dialectical philosophy determined by the Hegelian dialectic logic is demonstrated in this paper by differentiating Deleuze's interpretation of the problem of the infinitesimal in Difference and Repetition from that which G. W. F Hegel (1770-1831) presents in the Science of Logic . Each deploys the operation of integration as conceived at different stages in the development of the infinitesimal calculus in his (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hegel's theory of mental activity: an introduction to theoretical spirit.Willem A. DeVries - 1988 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    An interpretation of Hegel's Philosophy of Subjective Spirit showing its continued relevance to contemporary issues in the philosophy of mind.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Hegel and Sellars on the Unity of Things.Willem A. deVries - 2019 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 27 (3):363-378.
    ABSTRACTI have claimed previously that Hegel and Sellars are both, in the end, monistic visionaries, though with radically different visions of the grand unity of things. In this paper I explain an...
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Feuerbach's theory of object‐relations and its legacy in 20 th century post‐Hegelian philosophy.Jean-Philippe Deranty - 2015 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 53 (3):286-310.
    This paper focuses on the way in which Feuerbach's attempt to develop a naturalistic, realist remodeling of Hegel's relational ontology, which culminated in his own version of “sensualism”, led him to emphasize the vulnerability of the subject and the role of affectivity, thus making object‐dependence a constitutive feature of subjectivity. We find in Feuerbach the first lineaments of a philosophical theory of object‐relations, one that anticipates the well‐known psychological theory of the same name, but one that also offers a broader (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hegel’s Interpretation of the Liar Paradox.Franca D’Agostini & Elena Ficara - 2021 - History and Philosophy of Logic 43 (2):105-128.
    In his Lectures on the History of Philosophy, Hegel develops a subtle analysis of Megarian paradoxes: the Liar, the Veiled Man and the Sorites. In this paper, we focus on Hegel's interpretation of...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Integrating evolution: A contribution to the Christian doctrine of creation.Rudolf B. Brun - 1994 - Zygon 29 (3):275-296.
    Science has demonstrated that the universe creates itself through its own history. This history is the result of a probabilistic process, not a deterministic execution of a plan. Science has also documented that human beings are a result of this universal, probabilistic process of general evolution. At first sight, these results seem to contradict Christian teaching. According to the Bible, history is essentially the history of salvation. Human beings therefore are not an “accident of nature” but special creations to be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Der Ästhet Franz Rosenzweig: Beautiful Form and Religious Thought.Zachary Braiterman - 2001 - Journal of Jewish Thought and Philosophy 10 (1):145-169.
  • A brief history of continental realism.Lee Braver - 2012 - Continental Philosophy Review 45 (2):261-289.
    This paper explains the nature and origin of what I am calling Transgressive Realism, a middle path between realism and anti-realism which tries to combine their strengths while avoiding their weaknesses. Kierkegaard created the position by merging Hegel’s insistence that we must have some kind of contact with anything we can call real (thus rejecting noumena), with Kant’s belief that reality fundamentally exceeds our understanding; human reason should not be the criterion of the real. The result is the idea that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Spinoza, Marx, and Ilyenkov (who did not know Marx’s transcription of Spinoza).Bill Bowring - 2022 - Studies in East European Thought 74 (3):297-317.
    In this article I start with Marx's transcriptions of Spinoza, and the deep significance of what he transcribed, from the Theologico-Political Treatise and the Correspondence, and in what order. I contend that this demonstrates what was of particular interest and importance to him at that time. Second, I examine the presence, even if not explicit, of Spinoza in Marx's works, and turn to the question whether Marx was a Spinozist. I think he was. Third, I turn to Ilyenkov and his (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Allergologies Versus Homeopathies.Petar Bojanić - 2010 - Law and Critique 21 (1):1-16.
    This paper is a reconstruction of Levinas’ reading of Hegel and his understanding of violence. Combining Franz Rosenzweig’s reflections which concern the sick philosopher and Hegel’s state, as well as Derrida’s interpretation of the different attributes of violence, our aim is also to give full evidence of Derrida’s critical reading of Levinas. The first part illustrates the various classifications of the figures of violence from the different periods of Hegel’s life and the traces that these figures have left in Levinas’ (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Ultramodern Condition: On the Phenomenology of the Shadow as Transgression. [REVIEW]Bruce A. Arrigo - 2012 - Human Studies 35 (3):429-444.
    The ultramodern condition represents the "third wave" in postmodernist-inspired philosophy and cultural practice. Two of ultramodernism's critical theoretical components are the human/social forces, flows, and assemblages that sustain transgression; and the human/social intensities, fluctuations, and thresholds that make transcendence possible as both will and way. In the ultramodern age, then, transcendence is about overcoming and transforming the conditions (i.e., forces, flows, and assemblages) that co-produce harm-generating (i.e., transgressive) tendencies. This manuscript problematizes transgression by way of ultramodern theory. This critical investigation (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The death of God and Hegel's system of philosophy.Deland Anderson - 1996 - Sophia 35 (1):35-61.
  • Hegel on legal and moral responsibility.Mark Alznauer - 2008 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 51 (4):365 – 389.
    When Hegel first addresses moral responsibility in the Philosophy of Right, he presupposes that agents are only responsible for what they intended to do, but appears to offer little, if any, justification for this assumption. In this essay, I claim that the first part of the Philosophy of Right, “Abstract Right”, contains an implicit argument that legal or external responsibility (blame for what we have done) is conceptually dependent on moral responsibility proper (blame for what we have intended). This overlooked (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Experience and Content: Consequences of a Continuum Theory.W. M. Davies - 1996 - Avebury.
    This book is about experiential content: what it is; what kind of account can be given of it. I am concerned with identifying and attacking one main view - I call it the inferentialist proposal. This account is central to the philosophy of mind, epistemology and philosophy of science and perception. I claim, however, that it needs to be recast into something far more subtle and enriched, and I attempt to provide a better alternative in these pages. The inferentialist proposal (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation