Results for 'intentions'

1000+ found
Order:
See also
  1. Diana Baumrind This article continues Baumrind's development of argu-ments against the use of deception in research. Here she presents three ethical rules which proscribe deceptive practices and examines the costs of such deception to.Intentional Deception - forthcoming - Bioethics: Basic Writings on the Key Ethical Questions That Surround the Major, Modern Biological Possibilities and Problems.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  8
    Charles R. Johnson.Humean Intentions - 1998 - American Philosophical Quarterly 35 (2).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  13
    Paisley Livingston.O. F. Intentions - 2003 - In Jerrold Levinson (ed.), The Oxford handbook of aesthetics. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 275.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Must rational intentions maximize utility?Ralph Wedgwood - 2017 - Philosophical Explorations 20 (sup2):73-92.
    Suppose that it is rational to choose or intend a course of action if and only if the course of action maximizes some sort of expectation of some sort of value. What sort of value should this definition appeal to? According to an influential neo-Humean view, the answer is “Utility”, where utility is defined as a measure of subjective preference. According to a rival neo-Aristotelian view, the answer is “Choiceworthiness”, where choiceworthiness is an irreducibly normative notion of a course of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  5. Speaker Intentions in Context.Jeffrey C. King - 2012 - Noûs 48 (2):219-237.
  6.  78
    Sellars, we-intentions and ought-statements.Stefanie Dach - 2021 - Synthese 198 (5):4415-4439.
    My paper is concerned with the relation between ought-statements and intentions in Wilfrid Sellars’s philosophy. According to an entrenched view in Sellars scholarship, Sellars considers ought-statements as expressions of we-intentions. The aim of my paper is to question this reading and to propose an alternative. According to this alternative reading of Sellars, ought-statements are metalinguistic statements about the implication relations between intentions. I show that the entrenched understanding faces many unacknowledged problems and generates incompatibilities with Sellars’s commitments (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  7. Referential Intentions: A Response to Buchanan and Peet.Elmar Unnsteinsson - 2018 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 96 (3):610-615.
    Buchanan (2014) argues for a Gricean solution to well-known counterexamples to direct reference theories of content. Peet (2016) develops a way to change the counterexample so that it seems to speak against Buchanan’s own proposal. I argue that both theorists fail to notice a significant distinction between the kinds of cases at issue. Those appearing to count against direct reference theory must be described such that speakers have false beliefs about the identity of the object to which they intend to (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  8. Actions, intentions, and consequences: The doctrine of doing and allowing.Warren S. Quinn - 1989 - Philosophical Review 98 (3):287-312.
  9.  19
    The Intentions of Intentionality and Other New Models for Modalities.D. E. Over - 1977 - Philosophical Quarterly 27 (106):81-82.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  10. We-Intentions.Raimo Tuomela & Kaarlo Miller - 1988 - Philosophical Studies 53 (3):367-389.
  11.  72
    Good intentions aside: Drafting a functionalist look at codes of ethics.Johannes Brinkmann & Knut Ims - 2003 - Business Ethics, the Environment and Responsibility 12 (3):265–274.
  12.  44
    Directing intentions.John Perry - 2010 - In Joseph Almog & Paolo Leonardi (eds.), The philosophy of David Kaplan. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 187--201.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  13. The Intentions of Intentionality and Other New Models for Modalities.Jaakko Hintikka - 1979 - Synthese 42 (2):315-334.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  14. Directing intentions.John Perry - 2019 - In Studies in language and information. Stanford, California: Center for the Study of Language and Information.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15. Intentions and impositions.Christian Knudsen - 1982 - In Norman Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny & Jan Pinborg (eds.), Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 479--95.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  16. Whistleblowing in Organizations: An Examination of Correlates of Whistleblowing Intentions, Actions, and Retaliation.Jessica R. Mesmer-Magnus & Chockalingam Viswesvaran - 2005 - Journal of Business Ethics 62 (3):277-297.
    Whistleblowing on organizational wrongdoing is becoming increasingly prevalent. What aspects of the person, the context, and the transgression relate to whistleblowing intentions and to actual whistleblowing on corporate wrongdoing? Which aspects relate to retaliation against whistleblowers? Can we draw conclusions about the whistleblowing process by assessing whistleblowing intentions? Meta-analytic examination of 193 correlations obtained from 26 samples (N = 18,781) reveals differences in the correlates of whistleblowing intentions and actions. Stronger relationships were found between personal, contextual, and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  17. Speaker intentions and intentionality.Michael Haugh & Kasia M. Jaszczolt - 2012 - In Keith Allan & Kasia Jaszczolt (eds.), Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics. Cambridge University Press. pp. 87--112.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18.  55
    Considering Intentions in Decision Making: What Is So Odd about It?Anton Markoč - 2017 - Journal of Social Philosophy 48 (4):481-498.
    An influential objection to the view that intentions are non-derivatively relevant to the moral permissibility of actions states that if intentions were relevant to permissibility in such a way, one would have to take them into account in decision making, which would be odd (in some morally relevant sense of ‘oddness’). The paper outlines and assesses three candidates for the oddness: that considering intentions in decision making is an unordinary practice, that it is impossible or conceptually confused, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Intentions in words.Herman Cappelen - 1999 - Noûs 33 (1):92-102.
    Philosophers take a great deal of interest in the study of meaning, reference, truth and other semantic properties, but remarkably little attention has been paid to the entities that have semantic properties. The view that’s typically taken for granted has two closely related components.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  20.  78
    On snubbing proximal intentions.Alfred R. Mele - 2019 - Philosophical Studies 176 (11):2833-2853.
    In the simplest case, a proximal intention is an intention one has now to do something now. Recently, some philosophers have argued that proximal intentions do much less work than they are sometimes regarded as doing. This article rebuts these arguments, explains why the concept of proximal intentions is important for some scientific work on intentional action, and sketches an empirical approach to identifying proximal intentions. Ordinary usage of “intend” and the place of intention in folk psychology (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  10
    Quantum Theory and Free Will: How Mental Intentions Translate into Bodily Actions.Henry P. Stapp - 2017 - Cham: Imprint: Springer.
    This book explains, in simple but accurate terms, how orthodox quantum mechanics works. The author, a distinguished theoretical physicist, shows how this theory, realistically interpreted, assigns an important role to our conscious free choices. Stapp claims that mainstream biology and neuroscience, despite nearly a century of quantum physics, still stick essentially to failed classical precepts in which mental intentions have no effect upon our bodily actions. He shows how quantum mechanics provides a rational basis for a better understanding of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  22.  72
    Intentions in Communication.Philip R. Cohen, Jerry Morgan & Martha E. Pollack - 1992 - Philosophical Quarterly 42 (167):245.
  23. Intentions in Communication.Philip R. Cohen Jerry Morgan & Martha Pollack (eds.) - 1990 - MIT Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  24.  84
    Promises, Intentions, and Reasons for Action.Andrew Lichter - 2021 - Ethics 132 (1):218-231.
    Abraham Roth argues that to accept a promise is to intend the performance of the promised action. I argue that this proposal runs into trouble because it makes it hard to explain how promises provide reasons for the performance of the promised action. Then, I ask whether we might fill the gap by saying that a promisor becomes entitled to the reasons for which her promise is accepted. I argue that this fix would implausibly shrink the class of binding promises (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  21
    Entrepreneurship Education and Entrepreneurial Intentions of College Students: The Mediating Role of Entrepreneurial Self-Efficacy and the Moderating Role of Entrepreneurial Competition Experience.Lihao Wu, Suo Jiang, Xiaomin Wang, Linwei Yu, Yansu Wang & Hui Pan - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    This study aims to explore effective ways to improve college students’ entrepreneurial self-efficacy and intentions through entrepreneurship education. The survey used a random sample of 804 college students in Zhejiang Province, China. The results show that: In terms of the characteristics of entrepreneurial intention, there are significant differences in gender, entrepreneurial experience, entrepreneurial competition experience, and family background of self-employment. There are significant differences in the characteristics of entrepreneurship education in gender, entrepreneurial competition experience, and the family background of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. Intentions and act evaluations.Michael Stocker - 1970 - Journal of Philosophy 67 (17):589-602.
  27. No Intentions in the Brain: A Wittgensteinian Perspective on the Science of Intention.Annemarie Kalis - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
  28. Intentions, indexicals and communication.Stefano Predelli - 2002 - Analysis 62 (4):310–316.
  29.  26
    Influences of visibility, intentions, and probability in a peripheral cuing task.U. Ansorge - 2002 - Consciousness and Cognition 11 (4):528-545.
    According to the concept of direct parameter specification, nonconsciously registered information can be processed to the extent that it matches currently active intentions of a person. This prediction was tested and confirmed in the current study. Masked visual information provided by peripheral cues led to reaction time effects only if the information specified one of the required responses . Information delivered by the same masked cues that did not match the intentions was not used. However, the same information (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  30.  47
    Intentions Revisited.W. V. O. Quine - 1979 - In Peter A. French, T. E. Uehuling Jr & Howard K. Wettstein (eds.), Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language. University of Minnesota Press. pp. 5-11.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  31. Wrongful Intentions without Closeness.Victor Tadros - 2015 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 43 (1):52-74.
  32. Mill's Intentions and Motives.Michael Ridge - 2002 - Utilitas 14 (1):54.
    One might have thought that any right-thinking utilitarian would hold that motives and intentions are morally on a par, as either might influence the consequences of one's actions. However, in a neglected passage of Utilitarianism, John Stuart Mill claims that the rightness of an action depends 'entirely upon the intention' but does not at all depend upon the motive. In this paper I try to make sense of Mill's initially puzzling remarks about the relative importance of intentions and (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  33. Surrogates and Empty Intentions: Husserl’s “On the Logic of Signs” as the Blueprint for his First Logical Investigation.Thomas Byrne - 2017 - Husserl Studies 33 (3):211-227.
    This paper accomplishes two tasks. First, I examine in detail Edmund Husserl’s earliest philosophy of surrogates, as it is found in his 1890 “On the Logic of Signs ”. I analyze his psychological and logical investigations of surrogates, where the former is concerned with explaining how these signs function and the latter with how they do so reliably. His differentiation of surrogates on the basis of their genetic origins and degrees of necessity is discussed. Second, the historical importance of this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  34. Recognizing communicative intentions in infancy.Gergely Csibra - 2010 - Mind and Language 25 (2):141-168.
    I make three related proposals concerning the development of receptive communication in human infants. First, I propose that the presence of communicative intentions can be recognized in others' behaviour before the content of these intentions is accessed or inferred. Second, I claim that such recognition can be achieved by decoding specialized ostensive signals. Third, I argue on empirical bases that, by decoding ostensive signals, human infants are capable of recognizing communicative intentions addressed to them. Thus, learning about (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  35.  19
    Intentions, awareness, and awareness thereof.Lawrence H. Davis - 1978 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (4):566-567.
  36.  24
    Intentions vs. resemblance: Understanding pictures in typical development and autism.Calum Hartley & Melissa L. Allen - 2014 - Cognition 131 (1):44-59.
  37. Divine Intentions and the Problem of Evil.Justin Mooney - 2019 - Religious Studies 55 (2):215-234.
    I develop a model of providence on which God brings about good states of affairs by means of evil states of affairs, but without intending the latter. The model's key ingredient is a backward-looking counterpart of the distinction between intended and merely foreseen consequences of an action: namely, a distinction between intended and merely foreseen means to an end. The model enables greater-good theodicies to avoid worries about whether a perfect being could intend evil.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Meaning without Gricean Intentions.Pavese Carlotta & Radulescu Alexandru - forthcoming - Analysis.
    Gricean theories analyse meaning in terms of certain complex intentions on the part of the speaker—the intention to produce an effect on the addressee, and the intention to have that intention recognized by the addressee. By drawing an analogy with cases widely discussed in action theory, we propose a novel counterexample where the speaker lacks these intentions, but nonetheless means something, and successfully performs a speech act.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Propositions as Intentions.Bruno Bentzen - 2023 - Husserl Studies 39 (2):143-160.
    I argue against the interpretation of propositions as intentions and proof-objects as fulfillments proposed by Heyting and defended by Tieszen and van Atten. The idea is already a frequent target of criticisms regarding the incompatibility of Brouwer’s and Husserl’s positions, mainly by Rosado Haddock and Hill. I raise a stronger objection in this paper. My claim is that even if we grant that the incompatibility can be properly dealt with, as van Atten believes it can, two fundamental issues indicate (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40. Reporting and Interpreting Intentions in Defamation Law.Fabrizio Macagno - 2015 - In Alessandro Capone, Ferenc Kiefer & Franco Lo Piparo (eds.), Indirect Reports and Pragmatics. Cham: Imprint: Springer. pp. 593-619.
    The interpretation and the indirect reporting of a speaker’s communicative intentions lie at the crossroad between pragmatics, argumentation theory, and forensic linguistics. Since the leading case Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., in the United States the legal problem of determining the truth of a quotation is essentially equated with the correctness of its indirect reporting, i.e. the representation of the speaker’s intentions. For this reason, indirect reports are treated as interpretations of what the speaker intends to communicate. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41.  54
    Predictors of Usage Intentions of Pirated Software.Ian Phau & James Ng - 2010 - Journal of Business Ethics 94 (1):23-37.
    The purpose of this study is to investigate the salient factors influencing consumers’ attitudes and usage intentions towards pirated software. Using the Theory of Planned Behaviour, this study investigates the relationships between three sets of factors, i.e. personal, social and perceived behavioural control onto attitudes towards pirated software. Through a multiple regression, only personal factors have shown significant relationship with attitudes towards software piracy. Further results from this study have supported that favourable attitudes towards pirated software is likely to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  42.  43
    Reseña de "Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will" de Mele, Alfred R.Flor Emilce Cely Ávila - 2009 - Ideas Y Valores 58 (141):246-250.
  43.  49
    Intentions and self-referential content.Tomis Kapitan - 1995 - Philosophical Papers 24 (3):151-166.
  44.  68
    Temptation, Monetary Intelligence (Love of Money), and Environmental Context on Unethical Intentions and Cheating.Jingqiu Chen, Thomas Li-Ping Tang & Ningyu Tang - 2014 - Journal of Business Ethics 123 (2):197-219.
    In Study 1, we test a theoretical model involving temptation, monetary intelligence (MI), a mediator, and unethical intentions and investigate the direct and indirect paths simultaneously based on multiple-wave panel data collected in open classrooms from 492 American and 256 Chinese students. For the whole sample, temptation is related to low unethical intentions indirectly. Multi-group analyses reveal that temptation predicts unethical intentions both indirectly and directly for male American students only; but not for female American students. For (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  45.  34
    Stress and Turnover Intentions Within Healthcare Teams: The Mediating Role of Psychological Safety, and the Moderating Effect of COVID-19 Worry and Supervisor Support.Melany Hebles, Francisco Trincado-Munoz & Karina Ortega - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    Employees at healthcare organizations are experiencing more stress than ever given the current COVID-19 pandemic. Different types of stress are affecting diverse organizational outcomes, including the employees’ voluntary turnover. This is the case of cognitive stress, a type of stress that affects how individuals process information, which can influence employees’ turnover intentions. In this study, we look at the mechanisms that can reduce the adverse effects of cognitive stress on turnover intentions, particularly the role of employees’ perceived psychological (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  58
    Self-deceiving intentions.Mike W. Martin - 1997 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (1):122-123.
    Contrary to Mele's suggestion, not all garden-variety self-deception reduces to bias-generated false beliefs (usually held contrary to the evidence). Many cases center around self-deceiving intentions to avoid painful topics, escape unpleasant truths, seek comfortable attitudes, and evade self-acknowledgment. These intentions do not imply paradoxical projects or contradictory belief states.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  47. Utterer’s Meaning and Intentions.H. Paul Grice - 1969 - Philosophical Review 78 (2):147-177.
  48. Acts, intentions, and moral permissibility: In defence of the doctrine of double effect.William J. FitzPatrick - 2003 - Analysis 63 (4):317–321.
  49.  16
    Cognitive Primitives of Collective Intentions: Linguistic Evidence of Our Mental Ontology.Daniel Harbour Natalie Gold - 2012 - Mind and Language 27 (2):109-134.
    Theories of collective intentions must distinguish genuinely collective intentions from coincidentally harmonized ones. Two apparently equally apt ways of doing so are the ‘neo-reductionism’ of Bacharach (2006) and Gold and Sugden (2007a) and the ‘non-reductionism’ of Searle (1990, 1995). Here, we present findings from theoretical linguistics that show that we is not a cognitive primitive, but is composed of notions of I and grouphood. The ramifications of this finding on the structure both of grammatical and lexical systems suggests (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  96
    Consistency Among Intentions and the ‘Simple View’.Steven Sverdlik - 1996 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26 (4):515-522.
    What is the relation between the intention to A and doing A intentionally? It is natural to suppose that the latter entails the former. That is, it is natural to accept what Michael Bratman has called the ‘Simple View’ of the relation between acting intentionally and having an intention. Bratman is one noteworthy writer who has denied that the Simple View is true. In the present paper I do not defend this view. I contend that one well-known argument that Bratman (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000