Results for 'knowledge requirement'

999 found
Order:
  1. No knowledge required.Kevin Reuter & Peter Brössel - 2018 - Episteme 16 (3):303-321.
    Assertions are the centre of gravity in social epistemology. They are the vehicles we use to exchange information within scientific groups and society as a whole. It is therefore essential to determine under which conditions we are permitted to make an assertion. In this paper we argue and provide empirical evidence for the view that the norm of assertion is justified belief: truth or even knowledge are not required. Our results challenge the knowledge account advocated by, e.g. Williamson (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  2. Self-Knowledge Requirements and Moore's Paradox.David James Barnett - 2021 - Philosophical Review 130 (2):227-262.
    Is self-knowledge a requirement of rationality, like consistency, or means-ends coherence? Many claim so, citing the evident impropriety of asserting, and the alleged irrationality of believing, Moore-paradoxical propositions of the form < p, but I don't believe that p>. If there were nothing irrational about failing to know one's own beliefs, they claim, then there would be nothing irrational about Moore-paradoxical assertions or beliefs. This article considers a few ways the data surrounding Moore's paradox might be marshaled to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Knowledge requires belief – and it doesn’t? On belief as such and belief necessary for knowledge.Peter Baumann - 2019 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 62 (2):151-167.
    ABSTRACTDoes knowledge entail belief? This paper argues that the answer depends on how one interprets ‘belief’. There are two different notions of belief: belief as such and belief for knowledge. They often differ in their degrees of conviction such that one but not both might be present in a particular case. The core of the paper is dedicated to a defense of this overlooked distinction. The beginning of the paper presents the distinction. It then presents two cases which (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  92
    Knowledge requires commitment (instead of belief).Nicholas Tebben - 2019 - Philosophical Studies 176 (2):321-338.
    I argue that S knows that p implies that S is properly committed to the truth of p, not that S believes that p. Belief is not required for knowledge because it is possible that one could know that there are no beliefs. Being ‘properly committed’ to the truth of a proposition is a matter of having a certain normative status, not occupying a particular psychological state. After arguing that knowledge requires commitment instead of belief, I go on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  5.  24
    Does Knowledge Require Grounds?John Turk Saunders - 1966 - Philosophical Studies 17 (1/2):7 - 13.
  6.  22
    Knowledge Requiring Emotions.John Tietz - 1975 - Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 6 (3):155-158.
  7.  22
    Does knowledge require grounds?John Turksaunders - 1966 - Philosophical Studies 17 (1-2):7-13.
  8.  8
    Expertise and Knowledge Required to Support Health Staff to Manage Stressful Events.Clare Delany, Sarah Jones, Jenni Sokol, Lynn Gillam & Trisha Prentice - 2022 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 19 (4):535-536.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  88
    Does observational knowledge require metaknowledge? A dialogue on Sellars.Timm Triplett & Willem deVries - 2007 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 15 (1):23 – 51.
    In the following dialogue between TT - a foundationalist - and WdeV - a Sellarsian, we offer our differing assessments of the principle for observational knowledge proposed in Wilfrid Sellars's 'Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind'. Sellars writes: 'For a Konstatierung "This is green" to "express observational knowledge", not only must it be a symptom or sign of the presence of a green object in standard conditions, but the perceiver must know that tokens of "This is green" are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  10.  7
    On the knowledge requirements of tasks.Ronen I. Brafman, Joseph Y. Halpern & Yoav Shoham - 1998 - Artificial Intelligence 98 (1-2):317-349.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  1
    On the knowledge required to label a picture graph.Eugene C. Freuder - 1980 - Artificial Intelligence 15 (1-2):1-17.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  61
    Sophisticated knowledge representation and reasoning requires philosophy.Selmer Bringsjord, Micah Clark & Joshua Taylor - forthcoming - In Ruth Hagengruber (ed.), Philosophy's Relevance in Information Science.
    Knowledge Representation and Reasoning (KR&R) is based on the idea that propositional content can be rigorously represented in formal languages long the province of logic, in such a way that these representations can be productively reasoned over by humans and machines; and that this reasoning can be used to produce knowledge-based systems (KBSs). As such, KR&R is a discipline conventionally regarded to range across parts of artificial intelligence (AI), computer science, and especially logic. This standard view of KR&R’s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. ``Understanding, Knowledge, and the M eno Requirement".Wayne D. Riggs - 2009 - In Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar & Duncan Pritchard (eds.), Epistemic Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  14. Embodied savoir-faire: knowledge-how requires motor representations.Neil Levy - 2017 - Synthese 194 (2).
    I argue that the intellectualist account of knowledge-how, according to which agents have the knowledge-how to \ in virtue of standing in an appropriate relation to a proposition, is only half right. On the composition view defended here, knowledge-how at least typically requires both propositional knowledge and motor representations. Motor representations are not mere dispositions to behavior because they have representational content, and they play a central role in realizing the intelligence in knowledge-how. But since (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  15. Understanding, knowledge, and the meno requirement Wayne D. Riggs.Wayne Riggs - manuscript
    Jonathan Kvanvig's book, The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding (Kvanvig, 2003), is a wonderful example of doing epistemology in a style that Kvanvig himself has termed "value−driven epistemology." On this approach, one takes questions about epistemic value to be central to theoretical concerns, including the concern to provide an adequate account of knowledge. This approach yields the demand that theories of knowledge must provide, not just an adequate account of the nature of knowledge, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  16. Does linguistic competence require knowledge of language?Robert J. Matthews - 2003 - In Alex Barber (ed.), Epistemology of language. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  17.  14
    Knowledge Doesn’t Require Epistemic Certainty.James Simpson - 2019 - Logos and Episteme 10 (4):449-450.
    In a recent discussion note in this journal, Moti Mizrahi offers us the following argument for the conclusion that knowledge requires epistemic certainty:1) If S knows that p on the grounds that e, then p cannot be false given e.2) If p cannot be false given e, then e makes p epistemically certain.3) Therefore, if S knows that p on the grounds that e, then e makes p epistemically certain. I’ll argue that premise 2 of Mizrahi’s argument is false, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  61
    Is Knowledge of Essence Required for Thinking about Something?Daniele Sgaravatti - 2016 - Dialectica 70 (2):217-228.
    Lowe claims that having knowledge of the essence of an object is a precondition for thinking about it. Lowe supports this claim with roughly the following argument: you cannot think about something unless you know what you are thinking about; and to know what it is that you are thinking about just is to know its essence. I will argue that this line of reasoning fails because of an equivocation in the expression ‘what a thing is’, which can be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  19.  10
    Knowledge and ethics in anthropology: obligations and requirements.Lisette Josephides (ed.) - 2015 - New York, NY: Bloomsbury Academic, an imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing, Plc.
    This volume explores the anthropology of knowledge. Inspired by eminent scholar Marilyn Strathern, leading anthropologists explore key theoretical themes of subjectivity, ethics and gender through global ethnographies.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  45
    "Inexplicable knowledge" does not require belief.D. S. Mannison - 1976 - Philosophical Quarterly 26 (103):139-148.
  21.  62
    What Does Knowledge-yielding Deduction Require Of Its Premises?Federico Luzzi - 2014 - Episteme 11 (3):261-275.
    According to the principle of Knowledge Counter-Closure , knowledge-yielding single-premise deduction requires a known premise: if S believes q solely on the basis of deduction from p, and S knows q, then S must know p. Although prima facie plausible, widely accepted, and supported by seemingly compelling motivations, KCC has recently been challenged by cases where S arguably knows q solely on the basis of deduction from p, yet p is false or p is true but not known (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  22. Does Moral Virtue Require Knowledge? A Response to Julia Driver.Michael Jeffrey Winter - 2012 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15 (4):533 - 546.
    A long-standing tenet of virtue theory is that moral virtue and knowledge are connected in some important way. Julia Driver attacks the traditional assumption that virtue requires knowledge. I argue that the examples of virtues of ignorance Driver offers are not compelling and that the idea that knowledge is required for virtue has been taken to be foundational for virtue theory for good reason. I propose that we understand modesty as involving three conditions: 1) having genuine accomplishments, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  23.  9
    What conception of knowledge does the epistemic version of deliberative democracy require? A classification proposal.Nicolás Alles - 2019 - Ideas Y Valores 68 (171):161-184.
    RESUMEN El presente artículo intenta desarrollar los elementos de una concepción del conocimiento que resulte operativa para una versión epistémica de la democracia deliberativa. Se intenta superar algunas limitaciones de los modelos epistémico-deliberativos actuales y profundizar la relación entre conocimiento, deliberación y legitimidad. ABSTRACT The article develops the elements of a conception of knowledge that turns out to be operative for an epistemic version of deliberative democracy. It attempts to overcome some of the limitations of current deliberative-epistemic models and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  33
    The Social Value of Knowledge and the Responsiveness Requirement for International Research.Danielle M. Wenner - 2017 - Bioethics 31 (2):97-104.
    Ethicists have long recognized that two necessary features of ethical research are scientific validity and social value. Yet despite a significant literature surrounding the validity component of this dictate, until recently there has been little attention paid to unpacking what the social value component might require. This article introduces a framework for assessing the social value of research, and in particular, for determining whether a given research program is likely to have significant social value of the kind necessary to fulfill (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  25.  25
    Do Knowledge, Ethics, and Liberty Require Free Will? [REVIEW]William Dwyer - 2001 - Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 3 (1):83 - 108.
    William Dwyer reviews Initiative: Human Agency and Society, in which Tibor Machan argues that free will is a prerequisite for knowledge, ethics, and political liberty. Machan criticizes Hayek, Stigler, and "public choice" economics for their economic determinism and for discounting the importance of abstract ideas. Despite making a good case against environmental and economic determinism, Machan fails adequately to defend his central thesis that free will exists and that it is required for normative values.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26. Knowledge is Believing Something Because It's True.Tomas Bogardus & Will Perrin - 2022 - Episteme 19 (2):178-196.
    Modalists think that knowledge requires forming your belief in a “modally stable” way: using a method that wouldn't easily go wrong, or using a method that wouldn't have given you this belief had it been false. Recent Modalist projects from Justin Clarke-Doane and Dan Baras defend a principle they call “Modal Security,” roughly: if evidence undermines your belief, then it must give you a reason to doubt the safety or sensitivity of your belief. Another recent Modalist project from Carlotta (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  27.  31
    Popper’s Third Requirement for the Growth of Knowledge.Husain Sarkar - 1981 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 19 (4):489-497.
    In Section 5 of his important paper, “Truth, Rationality, and the Growth of Knowledge,”’ Karl Popper discusses the requirements for knowledge to grow. According to Popper, a scientist often finds himself in the following problem-situation: A theory T that he has been using so far, while it can explain some facts, cannot explain others, and is falsified by still other facts. Consequently, the scientist desires to come up with a theory T‘ that will explain everything that T could (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Mighty Knowledge.Bob Beddor & Simon Goldstein - 2021 - Journal of Philosophy 118 (5):229-269.
    We often claim to know what might be—or probably is—the case. Modal knowledge along these lines creates a puzzle for information-sensitive semantics for epistemic modals. This paper develops a solution. We start with the idea that knowledge requires safe belief: a belief amounts to knowledge only if it could not easily have been held falsely. We then develop an interpretation of the modal operator in safety that allows it to non-trivially embed information-sensitive contents. The resulting theory avoids (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29. Knowledge, adequacy, and approximate truth.Wesley Buckwalter & John Turri - 2020 - Consciousness and Cognition 83 (C):102950.
    Approximation involves representing things in ways that might be close to the truth but are nevertheless false. Given the widespread reliance on approximations in science and everyday life, here we ask whether it is conceptually possible for false approximations to qualify as knowledge. According to the factivity account, it is impossible to know false approximations, because knowledge requires truth. According to the representational adequacy account, it is possible to know false approximations, if they are close enough to the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  30.  22
    A methodological requirement in the investigation of “knowledge”.Mark John O'Brien - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (5):779-780.
    The modernist and scientific juxtaposition of object and subject are inappropriate when investigating the nature of “knowledge.” This commentary argues that the usual methodological dichotomy fails when it is applied to the domain of “knowledge.” The two instead coalesce within the topic itself, demanding the most careful self-awareness.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Practical Knowledge without Luminosity.Bob Beddor & Carlotta Pavese - 2021 - Mind 131 (523):917-934.
    According to a rich tradition in philosophy of action, intentional action requires practical knowledge: someone who acts intentionally knows what they are doing while they are doing it. Piñeros Glasscock argues that an anti-luminosity argument, of the sort developed in Williamson, can be readily adapted to provide a reductio of an epistemic condition on intentional action. This paper undertakes a rescue mission on behalf of an epistemic condition on intentional action. We formulate and defend a version of an epistemic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  32.  20
    Memory behavior requires knowledge structures, not memory stores.Guillermo Campitelli - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Knowledge claims and context: loose use.Wayne A. Davis - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 132 (3):395-438.
    There is abundant evidence of contextual variation in the use of “S knows p.” Contextualist theories explain this variation in terms of semantic hypotheses that refer to standards of justification determined by “practical” features of either the subject’s context (Hawthorne & Stanley) or the ascriber’s context (Lewis, Cohen, & DeRose). There is extensive linguistic counterevidence to both forms. I maintain that the contextual variation of knowledge claims is better explained by common pragmatic factors. I show here that one is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  34.  13
    Popper's Third Requirement for the Growth of Knowledge.Husain Sarkar - 1981 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 19 (4):489-497.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Benchmark programs for evaluating knowledge-based performance requirements.Mary M. Hayes Karen L. Ruoff - forthcoming - Annual Ai Systems in Government Conference: Proceedings.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Obligations and Requirements : The Contexts of Knowledge.Lisette Josephides - 2015 - In Knowledge and ethics in anthropology: obligations and requirements. New York, NY: Bloomsbury Academic, an imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing, Plc.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Knowledge and evidence.Paul K. Moser - 1989 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Paul Moser's book defends what has been an unfashionable view in recent epistemology: the foundationalist account of knowledge and justification. Since the time of Plato philosophers have wondered what exactly knowledge is. This book develops a new account of perceptual knowledge which specifies the exact sense in which knowledge has foundations. The author argues that experiential foundations are indeed essential to perceptual knowledge, and he explains what knowledge requires beyond justified true beliefs. In challenging (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  38.  61
    Challenging the epistemological foundations of EBM: what kind of knowledge does clinical practice require?Katrina J. Hutchison & Wendy A. Rogers - 2012 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 18 (5):984-991.
    This paper raises questions about the epistemological foundations of evidence-based medicine . We argue that EBM is based upon reliabilist epistemological assumptions, and that this is appropriate - we should focus on identifying the most reliable processes for generating and collecting medical knowledge. However, we note that this should not be reduced to narrow questions about which research methodologies are the best for gathering evidence. Reliable processes for generating medical evidence might lie outside of formal research methods. We also (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  39.  56
    Knowledge Is Belief For Sufficient (Objective and Subjective) Reason.Mark Schroeder - 2015 - Oxford Studies in Epistemology 5.
    This chapter lays out a case that with the proper perspective on the place of epistemology within normative inquiry more generally, it is possible to appreciate what was on the right track about some of the early approaches to the analysis of knowledge, and to improve on the obvious failures which led them to be rejected. Drawing on more general principles about reasons, their weight, and their relationship to justification, it offers answers to problems about defeat and the conditional (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  40.  77
    Knowledge puzzles: an introduction to epistemology.Stephen Cade Hetherington - 1996 - Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press.
    Despite the problems students often have with the theory of knowledge, it remains, necessarily, at the core of the philosophical enterprise. As experienced teachers know, teaching epistemology requires a text that is not only clear and accessible, but also capable of successfully motivating the abstract problems that arise.In Knowledge Puzzles, Stephen Hetherington presents an informal survey of epistemology based on the use of puzzles to illuminate problems of knowledge. Each topic is introduced through a puzzle, and readers (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  41.  23
    Gertler's acquaintance approach to introspective knowledge and internalist requirements for reasons.Byeong D. Lee - forthcoming - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy.
    Gertler argues that, in some introspective judgments about experience, phenomenal reality intersects with one's grasp of that reality to the effect that one can have knowledge by acquaintance. This new version of the acquaintance theory depends on the idea that some introspective judgments about experience can be justified by the fact that the phenomenal property of an experience is a component of the introspective judgment about the experience. The goal of this paper is to show that even this most (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Knowledge and Evidence.Paul K. Moser - 1989 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Paul Moser's book defends what has been an unfashionable view in recent epistemology: the foundationalist account of knowledge and justification. Since the time of Plato philosophers have wondered what exactly knowledge is. This book develops a new account of perceptual knowledge which specifies the exact sense in which knowledge has foundations. The author argues that experiential foundations are indeed essential to perceptual knowledge, and he explains what knowledge requires beyond justified true beliefs. In challenging (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  43. Knowledge-how: A unified account.Berit Brogaard - 2011 - In J. Bengson & M. Moffett (eds.), Knowing How: Essays on Knowledge, Mind, and Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 136-160.
    There are two competing views of knowledge-how: Intellectualism and anti-intellectualism. According to the reductionist varieties of intellectualism defended by Jason Stanley and Timothy Williamson (2001) and Berit Brogaard (2007, 2008, 2009), knowledge-how simply reduces to knowledge-that. To a first approximation, s knows how to A iff there is a w such that s knows that w is a way to A. For example, John knows how to ride a bicycle if and only if there is a way (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  44.  57
    What Knowledge is Necessary for Virtue?Olivia Bailey - 2010 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 4 (2):1-18.
    Critics contend that Aristotelianism demands too much of the virtuous person in the way of knowledge to be credible. This general charge is usually directed against either of two of Aristotelianism’s apparent claims about the necessary conditions for the possession of a single virtue, namely that 1) one must know what all the other virtues require, and 2) one must also be the master of a preternatural range of technical/empirical knowledge. I argue that Aristotelianism does indeed have a (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  45.  21
    A Defence of the Manifestation Requirement: An Application of Anscombe's Theory of Practical Knowledge.Takeshi Yamada - 2022 - Journal of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 49 (2):111-130.
    The Manifestation Requirement, advanced by Dummett in his critique of semantic realism, has been criticized for being behavioristic, and the responses have been made that the critics are mistaken. However, the dispute has failed to exhibit the point of the Requirement. In this paper, I shall argue (1) that, in the light of Anscombe's theory of practical knowledge, knowledge of linguistic meaning is to be seen as the knowledge-how that forms the basis of the practical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Knowledge and truth: A skeptical challenge.Wesley Buckwalter & John Turri - 2019 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 101 (1):93-101.
    It is widely accepted in epistemology that knowledge is factive, meaning that only truths can be known. We argue that this theory creates a skeptical challenge: because many of our beliefs are only approximately true, and therefore false, they do not count as knowledge. We consider several responses to this challenge and propose a new one. We propose easing the truth requirement on knowledge to allow approximately true, practically adequate representations to count as knowledge. In (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  47. Knowledge is the Norm of Assertion.Matthew A. Benton - 2024 - In Blake Roeber, Ernest Sosa, Matthias Steup & John Turri (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 3rd edition. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 329-339.
    Assertion is governed by an epistemic norm requiring knowledge. This idea has been hotly debated in recent years, garnering attention in epistemology, philosophy of language, and linguistics. This chapter presents and extends the main arguments in favor of the knowledge norm, from faulty conjunctions, several conversational patterns, judgments of permission, excuse, and blame, and from showing how. (Paired with a chapter by Peter J. Graham and Nikolaj J. L. L. Pedersen, "Knowledge is Not Our Norm of Assertion.").
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  43
    Practical Knowledge, Equal Standing, and Proper Reliance on Others.Carla Bagnoli - 2020 - Theoria 86 (6):821-842.
    According to a traditional account, moral cognition is an achievement gained over time by sharing a practice under the guidance and the example of the wise, in analogy with craft and apprenticeship. This model captures an important feature of practical reason, that is, its incompleteness, and highlights our dependence on others in obtaining moral knowledge, coherently with the socially extended mind agenda and recent findings in empirical psychology. However, insofar as it accords to exemplars’ decisive authority to determine the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  26
    The architecture challenge: Future artificial-intelligence systems will require sophisticated architectures, and knowledge of the brain might guide their construction.Gianluca Baldassarre, Vieri Giuliano Santucci, Emilio Cartoni & Daniele Caligiore - 2017 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  3
    Poesia Mimética y Conocimiento. La crítica de Platón a los poetas y los requisitos epistemológicos para el nuevo discurso/Mimetic Poetry and Knowledge Plato´s criticism to the poets and the epistemological requirements from the new discourse.Esteban Guio Aguilar - 2014 - Pensando - Revista de Filosofia 4 (8):42.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 999