Results for 'Cartesian empiricism'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  8
    The cartesian empiricism of François Bayle.Thomas M. Lennon - 1992 - New York: Garland. Edited by Patricia Ann Easton.
  2.  47
    Desgabets as a cartesian empiricist.Monte Cook - 2008 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (4):pp. 501-515.
    A long tradition regards Robert Desgabets as a Cartesian empiricist. He says things that sound strikingly like Locke, and he argues against anti-empiricist reasoning in Descartes, Malebranche, and Arnauld. Moreover, throughout his writings he endorses the empiricist principle that nothing is in the intellect except what was previously in the senses. Since the Cartesians are generally supposed to be prototypical non -empiricists, Desgabets’s being a Cartesian empiricist would make him a particularly interesting specimen. In this paper, however, I (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  3.  6
    The Father of Cartesian Empiricism: Robert Desgabets on the physics and metaphysics of blood transfusion.Patricia Easton - unknown
    The period in the history of blood transfusion that I discuss is roughly 1628, the date of publication of Harvey’s work on blood circulation, De Motu Cordis, and 1668, the year of the first allegedly successful transfusion of blood into a human subject by a French physician Jean Denis, and the official order to prohibit the procedure. The subject of special interest in this history is Robert Desgabets, an early defender and teacher of the Cartesian philosophy at St. Maur, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Desgabets: Rationalist or Cartesian Empiricist?Sean Allen-Hermanson - 2008 - In Jon Miller (ed.), Topics in Early Modern Philosophy of Mind (Springer).
  5.  11
    The Cartesian Empiricism of Francois Bayle by Thomas M. Lennon; Patricia Ann Easton; The Battle of the Gods and Giants: The Legacies of Descartes and Gassendi, 1655-1715 by Thomas M. Lennon. [REVIEW]Steven Nadler - 1994 - Isis 85:695-696.
  6.  28
    The Cartesian Empiricism of Francois Bayle. Thomas M. Lennon, Patricia Ann EastonThe Battle of the Gods and Giants: The Legacies of Descartes and Gassendi, 1655-1715. Thomas M. Lennon. [REVIEW]Steven Nadler - 1994 - Isis 85 (4):695-696.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Thomas M. Lennon and Patricia Ann Easton, The Cartesian Empiricism of François Bayle Reviewed by.Nicholas Jolley - 1992 - Philosophy in Review 12 (4):269-271.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. What we know and how we know it: Cartesian meditations on some hard problems at the interface of science and empiricist philosophy.Michael LaFargue - manuscript
    Laboratory science is our only source of knowledge about the world as it is apart from our perceptions of the world. Empiricist philosophy, relying on evidence consisting in human perceptions, can only give us knowledge of phenomena making up the world-perceived, which recent neuroscience tells us is wholly and entirely constructed by our neuron-based human perceptual apparatus. In this light, empiricist philosophy should explicitly and fundamentally be reconceived as a method of thinking critically about phenomena, i.e. as a stripped down, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  15
    6. Bridging scientia and experience: the last evolution of Cartesian foundationalism.Andrea Strazzoni - 2018 - In Dutch Cartesianism and the Birth of Philosophy of Science: From Regius to ‘s Gravesande. Berlin-Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 126-170.
    The sixth chapter focuses on the evolution of Cartesianism in the last quarter of the seventeenth century in Leiden and Amsterdam, against the background of the emergence of alternative views in natural philosophy capable of replacing it as a dominant paradigm, namely, the experimental philosophy of Robert Boyle and the mathematical-experimental approach of Huygens and Newton. The last evolution of Cartesianism is reconstructed in this chapter by considering the ‘Cartesian empiricism’ of Burchard de Volder, and the reflections on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  21
    Bernard Lamy, Empiricism, and Cartesianism.Fred Ablondi - 2018 - History of European Ideas 44 (2):149-158.
    ABSTRACTBernard Lamy is frequently included among the Cartesian Empiricists of the second half of the seventeenth century. He has also been described as an Augustinian who dabbled in Cartesianism. While acknowledging that there are both empiricist and Augustinian elements in his thought, I argue that it ought not be forgotten that there are central components of his philosophy that are both anti-empiricist and in opposition to Augustine. My aim in this paper, though, is not critical; I hope to show (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  10
    The Testimony of Sense: Empiricism and the Essay from Hume to Hazlitt by Tim Milnes (review).Margaret Watkins - 2024 - Hume Studies 49 (1):175-180.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:The Testimony of Sense: Empiricism and the Essay from Hume to Hazlitt by Tim MilnesMargaret WatkinsTim Milnes. The Testimony of Sense: Empiricism and the Essay from Hume to Hazlitt. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019. Pp. viii + 278. Hardback. ISBN: 9780198812739. $91.00.In his brief autobiography, “My Own Life,” Hume reports that “almost all [his] life has been spent in literary pursuits and occupations” (E-MOL: xxxi). This (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  29
    Empiricist heresies in early modern medical thought.Charles T. Wolfe - 2010 - In Charles T. Wolfe & Ofer Gal (eds.), The Body as Object and Instrument of Knowledge. Embodied Empiricism in Early Modern Science. Springer. pp. 333--344.
    Vitalism, from its early modern to its Enlightenment forms (from Glisson and Willis to La Caze and Barthez), is notoriously opposed to intervention into the living sphere. Experiment, quantification, measurement are all ‘vivisectionist’, morally suspect and worse, they alter and warp the ‘life’ of the subject. They are good for studying corpses, not living individuals. This much is well known, and it has disqualified vitalist medicine from having a place in standard histories of medicine, until recent, post-Foucauldian maneuvers have sought (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  13.  37
    Reason and the French Revolution: Burke's Empiricism vs. Cartesian-style Deduction.George C. McElroy - 1996 - Lumen: Selected Proceedings From the Canadian Society for Eighteenth-Century Studies 15:97.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Traditional Empiricism, the Myth of the Given and Self-knowledge.Yakir Levin - 2005 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 8.
    Sellars’ Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind is a landmark in the history of modern epistemology. It is here that Sellars launches his celebrated and highly influential attack on the ”Myth of the Given”. But based on this attack Sellars also argues in this work for a radical alternative to the orthodox, neo-Cartesian conception of self-knowledge, an alternative that has become the prevalent conception. While it is fairly easy to discern the general contours of Sellars’ conception of self-knowledge, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  9
    Locke and British Empiricism.Louis E. Loeb - 2015 - In Matthew Stuart (ed.), A Companion to Locke. Hoboken, NJ, USA: Wiley. pp. 503–527.
    John Locke thought that the clearest idea of active power derives from observing the mind's command over its ideas and limbs; observing the transfer of motion in impact also gives us an idea of active power. Berkeley denied this latter claim: the (related) idea of causation is derived exclusively from the experience of willing ideas, of volitional activity; the concept of causality has no legitimate extension beyond spirits and their volitions. The malleability of empiricist theories of meaning, whether in the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  6
    «Is the soul always thinking?» Posterity of the theory of intensio et remissio formarum in the debate between Empiricists and Cartesians.David Simonetta - 2013 - Astérion 11.
    « Le bon sens est la chose du monde la mieux partagée. » Il n’est pas rare de voir dans l’incipit du Discours de la méthode un de ces énoncés cartésiens qui, par leur simplicité et leur transparence, marquèrent une rupture avec la technicité de la philosophie scolastique des siècles précédents. Pourtant, à se pencher sur les commentaires qui ont été produits de ce texte, dès sa publication, il apparaît que pour un certain nombre de contemporains de Descartes, il y (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Irish cartesian and proto-phenomenologist: The case of Berkeley.Tim Mooney - manuscript
    Comparatively recent scholarship suggests that George Berkeley cannot be seen solely or even chiefly as a British empiricist who is reacting to the materialistic implications of Locke’s Essay on Human Understanding. C.J. McCracken has shown how Berkeley is influenced by Malebranche’s theses concerning the dependence of bodies on God, without himself doubting the evidence of the senses. McCracken also shows how Berkeley reconstructs and reapplies Malebranche’s fideism.1 Harry Bracken has argued, most notably, that Berkeley espouses certain theses that set him (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  24
    Cartesian Metaphysics: The Scholastic Origins of Modern Philosophy (review).Patrick R. Frierson - 2001 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (2):292-294.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 39.2 (2001) 292-294 [Access article in PDF] Secada, Jorge. Cartesian Metaphysics: The Scholastic Origins of Modern Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000. Pp. xii + 333. Cloth, $59.95. Descartes scholars can welcome this book. Secada supports trends in scholarship that criticize seeing Descartes as merely an anti-skeptical foundationalist, and he challenges many prominent interpretations of Descartes's metaphysics. In addition, Secada helpfully (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Early modern empiricism.Silvia Manzo & Sofía Calvente - 2020 - Encyclopedia of Early Modern Philosophy and the Sciences.
    Broadly speaking, “empiricism” is a label that usually denotes an epistemological view that emphasizes the role that experience plays in forming concepts and acquiring and justifying knowledge. In contemporary philosophy, there are some authors who call themselves as empiricists, although there are differences in the way they define what experience consists in, how it is related to theory, and the role experience plays in discovering and justifying knowledge, etc. (e.g., Ayer 1936; Van Fraassen 2002). In contrast, in the early (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20. Empiricist Roots of Modern Psychology.Raymond Martin - unknown
    From the thirteenth through the sixteenth centuries, European philosophers were preoccupied with using their newfound access to Aristotle’s metaphysics and natural philosophy to develop an integrated account, hospitable to Christianity, of everything that was thought to exist, including God, pure finite spirits, the immaterial souls of humans, the natural world of organic objects and inorganic objects. This account included a theory of human mentality. In the sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries, first in astronomy and then, later, in physics, the tightly (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  37
    Cartesian Empiricisms.Mihnea Dobre & Tammy Nyden (eds.) - 2013 - Dordrecht: Springer Verlag.
    Mihnea Dobre, Tammy Nyden. to not only notice the “anomalies,” but able to develop more useful narratives that can fully incorporate them. This work is a first step towards that end. We do not put forward an alternative narrative ourselves, but ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  32
    Cartesian Linguistics. [REVIEW]R. J. B. - 1967 - Review of Metaphysics 20 (3):539-539.
    The excitement generated among philosophers by Chomsky's work arises not only from his contributions to the study of language but also from the ramifications of his work for general issues of epistemology and the philosophy of science. Chomsky has been attacking cherished dogmas of empiricism and its ally, behaviorism. He has suggested that Descartes—the favorite whipping boy of contemporary philosophers—and his theory of innate ideas provide a fruitful starting point for understanding and appreciating recent work in transformational linguistics. In (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. The Myth of Cartesian Rationalism: An Examination of Experience in le Grand, Desgabets, and Regis.Patricia Ann Easton - 1993 - Dissertation, The University of Western Ontario (Canada)
    Recent re-evaluation of the question of the exact role of experience in the Cartesian philosophy has emerged from many quarters. The metaphysical issue of innate ideas has been raised by such scholars as McRae and Miles, and a close examination of the role of empirical enquiry and methodology in Cartesian science have been undertaken by Clarke, Garber, Buchdahl and Laudan, to mention only a few. These recent reappraisals of the role of experience in Descartes's philosophy have been cast (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  17
    Cartesian Linguistics. [REVIEW]J. B. R. - 1967 - Review of Metaphysics 20 (3):539-539.
    The excitement generated among philosophers by Chomsky's work arises not only from his contributions to the study of language but also from the ramifications of his work for general issues of epistemology and the philosophy of science. Chomsky has been attacking cherished dogmas of empiricism and its ally, behaviorism. He has suggested that Descartes—the favorite whipping boy of contemporary philosophers—and his theory of innate ideas provide a fruitful starting point for understanding and appreciating recent work in transformational linguistics. In (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  48
    The Cartesian Roots of Berkeley's Account of Sensation.Melissa Frankel - 2017 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 55 (2):214-231.
    On the old story about early modern philosophy, Descartes is a “rationalist” who devalues the senses, and Berkeley an “empiricist” who rejects this. Berkeley plays into this story in his Notebooks, where he writes: “in vindication of the senses effectually to confute wt Descartes saith in ye last par. of the last Med: viz. that the senses oftener inform him falsly than truely”. But when we turn to this “last par.,” we find Descartes maintaining that “my senses report the truth (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  97
    Hume on the cartesian theory of substance.Daniel E. Flage & Ronald J. Glass - 1984 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 22 (4):497-508.
    While most of hume's criticisms of the doctrine of substance are epistemological and theory-Independent, We show that in "treatise" i.Iv.5, Hume develops a metaphysical criticism of the cartesian theory of substance. Using three of pierre bayle's arguments of his own ends, He argues that on an empiricist theory of meaning, The cartesian theory of substance is reduced to absurdity.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  7
    Hegel’s Cartesian Grounding of Political Philosophy.Shterna Friedman - 2022 - Studia Hegeliana 8:137-154.
    Hegel saw modern philosophy as internally divided between its metaphysics and epistemology, on the one hand, and its political philosophy, on the other. Descartes had developed a metaphysics of totality to ground the epistemological certainty of the cogito, treating true unity as a unity of opposites (a totality). But political philosophy, in its empiricist and formalist forms, relied on an impoverished conception of unity—treating it, respectively, as a mere aggregation of parts or as formal consistency. The Philosophy of Right thus (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  48
    Rationalism, Empiricism, and Pragmatism. [REVIEW]W. J. L. - 1971 - Review of Metaphysics 24 (3):535-535.
    This volume is intended for use in an undergraduate philosophy course employing the problems' approach. Chapter I provides a clear presentation of Cartesian rationalism. Following the exposition of Descartes' position, there is a section on the standard criticisms levelled by B. Russell. Aune defends the rationalist position with an outline of the traditional arguments for the validity of intuitive knowledge. Chapter I terminates with a list of "Study Questions" and an annotated bibliography suggesting further readings. Chapter II considers classical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  52
    The Delicate Empiricism of Goethe: Phenomenology as a Rigorous Science of Nature.Brent Dean Robbins - 2006 - Indo-Pacific Journal of Phenomenology 6 (sup1):1-13.
    Johann Wolfgang von Goethe's approach to natural scientific research has unmistakable parallels to phenomenology. These parallels are clear enough to allow one to say confidently that Goethe's delicate empiricism is indeed a phenomenology of nature. This paper examines how Goethe's criticisms of Newton anticipated Husserl's announcement of the crisis of the modern sciences, and it describes how Goethe, at a critical juncture in cultural history, addressed this emerging crisis through a scientific method that is virtually identical to the method (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  33
    Rationalism, Empiricism, and Pragmatism. [REVIEW]J. L. W. - 1971 - Review of Metaphysics 24 (3):535-535.
    This volume is intended for use in an undergraduate philosophy course employing the problems' approach. Chapter I provides a clear presentation of Cartesian rationalism. Following the exposition of Descartes' position, there is a section on the standard criticisms levelled by B. Russell. Aune defends the rationalist position with an outline of the traditional arguments for the validity of intuitive knowledge. Chapter I terminates with a list of "Study Questions" and an annotated bibliography suggesting further readings. Chapter II considers classical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. The mind-body problem in the origin of logical empiricism: Herbert Feigl and psychophysical parallelism.Michael Heidelberger - 2001 - In Paolo Parrini, Wes Salmon & Merrilee Salmon (eds.), Cogprints. Pittsburgh University Pres. pp. 233--262.
    In the 19th century, "Psychophysical Parallelism" was the most popular solution of the mind-body problem among physiologists, psychologists and philosophers. (This is not to be mixed up with Leibnizian and other cases of "Cartesian" parallelism.) The fate of this non-Cartesian view, as founded by Gustav Theodor Fechner, is reviewed. It is shown that Feigl's "identity theory" eventually goes back to Alois Riehl who promoted a hybrid version of psychophysical parallelism and Kantian mind-body theory which was taken up by (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  32. A Fundamental Ambiguity In The Cartesian Theory Of Ideas.Graciela De Pierris - 2002 - Manuscrito 25 (2):105-146.
    Traditionally the modern theory of ideas has been discussed primarily in reference to its alleged introduction of a veil of mental items between the mind and the world, which leads, through the empiricists, to radical skepticism about the existence of an external world. Here I propose to emphasize an entirely different aspect of the Cartesian theory of ideas which, in my view, is more fundamental in opening the empiricist path that leads to Hume’s radical skepticism. I argue that what (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. A Fundamental Ambiguity In The Cartesian Theory Of Ideas: Descartes And Leibniz On Intellectual Apprehension/ Uma Ambiguidade Fundamental Na Teoria Cartesiana Das Idéias: Descartes E Leibniz Sobre A Apreensão Intelectual.Graciela De Pierris - 2007 - Manuscrito 30 (2):383-422.
    Traditionally the modern theory of ideas has been discussed primarily in reference to its alleged introduction of a veil of mental items between the mind and the world, which leads, through the empiricists, to radical skepticism about the existence of an external world. Here I propose to emphasize an entirely different aspect of the Cartesian theory of ideas which, in my view, is more fundamental in opening the empiricist path that leads to Hume’s radical skepticism. I argue that what (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  43
    The Myth of Cartesian Privacy.H. O. Mounce - 2011 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 85 (4):577-587.
    Wittgenstein is often thought to have undermined the view, attributed to Descartes, that the mental is in a special sense private. In fact this idea of privacyis more plausibly attributed to the empiricists than to Descartes. Nor is Descartes’s own view one that can easily be dismissed. In particular, it can serve to correct a tendency, among Wittgenstein’s followers, to treat the mental in behavioristic terms. The point is illustrated by reference to an issue in Christian theology.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  6
    Technology, Science, and Inexact Knowledge: Bachelard's Non‐Cartesian Epistemology.Mary Tiles - 2005 - In Gary Gutting (ed.), Continental Philosophy of Science. Blackwell. pp. 155–175.
    This chapter contains section titled: Pragmatism Redirected From Knowledge Approximated to Approximate Knowledge Technology, Standardization, and Experimental Science Measurement and Orders of Magnitude Non‐Reductionism, Hierarchy, and Complexity Action, Progress, and Moving Beyond Cartesian Intellectualism.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  25
    Overcoming a Dualism of Concepts and Causes: The Basic Argument of “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind”.Robert Brandom - 2002 - In Richard M. Gale (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 263–281.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Sellars' Two‐Ply Account of Observation “Looks” Talk and Sellars' Diagnosis of the Cartesian Hypostatization of Appearances Two Confirmations of the Analysis of “Looks” Talk in Terms of the Two‐Ply Account of Observation A Rationalist Account of the Acquisition of Empirical Concepts Giving Theoretical Concepts an Observational Use Conclusion: On the Relation Between the Two Components.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  15
    The Ambiguous Role of Experience in Cartesian Science.Desmond M. Clarke - 1976 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1976:151 - 164.
    Descartes' methodology is ambiguous about the role of empirical evidence in science. This ambiguity does not derive from Rationalist qualms about the specifically empirical character of such evidence; for the apparant clash of experience and reason is explained by the need to re-interpret perceptions in terms of new theories, and by the frequently "contaminated" status of so-called experimental evidence. The ambiguity results, rather, from: (a) Descartes' predilection for "ordinary experience" rather than experiments as a source of warrant, and (b) the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  19
    Induction and Justification, an Investigation of Cartesian Procedures in the Philosophy of Knowledge. [REVIEW]B. T. - 1975 - Review of Metaphysics 28 (3):571-573.
    This work is a departure from traditional investigations of induction. Rather than consider issues related to the justification or construction of a scientific inductive logic, Professor Will exposes, evaluates, and rejects the epistemological framework within which work in the philosophy of induction is usually conducted. He argues that the frustrating difficulties faced in the philosophy of induction are endemic to that theory of knowledge which "resulted from the empiricist criticism and revision of the basic Cartesian view that knowledge is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Locke and Malebranche : intelligibility and empiricism.Nicholas Jolley - 2018 - In Philippe Hamou & Martine Pécharman (eds.), Locke and Cartesian Philosophy. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
  40.  9
    Flipping the Deck: On Totality and Infinity’s Transcendental/Empirical Puzzle.Jack Marsh - 2016 - Levinas Studies 10 (1):79-113.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Flipping the DeckOn Totality and Infinity’s Transcendental/Empirical PuzzleJack Marsh (bio)How does one perceive a transcendental condition?— Martin Kavka... if it is legitimate to hold Levinas to the standards that he himself imposes on certain other philosophers.— Robert BernasconiI do not believe that there is a transparency possible in method. Nor that philosophy might be possible as transparency.— Emmanuel LevinasThe question of the precise methodological status of the face has (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  4
    Locke and Descartes.Lisa Downing - 2015 - In Matthew Stuart (ed.), A Companion to Locke. Hoboken, NJ, USA: Wiley. pp. 100–120.
    In this chapter, John Locke's anti‐Cartesian stances on the difference between body and space, on whether the soul always thinks, on the possibility of thinking matter, all connect back to the basic opposition to Cartesian overreaching in regard to essences. The chapter presents a summary of Locke's anti‐Cartesianism, which seems to fit with his own representation of his Cartesian inheritance, which, notoriously, is that it is minimal, consisting only in anti‐scholasticism. The only acknowledgment that Locke wishes to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  11
    Stroud's Camap.Marc Alspector-Kelly - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (2):276-302.
    In “Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology” Camap drew his famous distinction between ‘internal’ and ‘external’ questions of existence, pronouncing the former meaningful and the latter meaningless. In The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism, Barry Stroud understands Carnap to be applying the verification criterion of meaningfulness in order to refute Cartesian skepticism. I suggest that Stroud misrepresents both Carnap's aim and method. Camap was responding to critics who suggested that his willingness to quantify over abstract entities in his work in semantics (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  17
    Stroud's Camap.Marc Alspector-Kelly - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (2):276-302.
    In “Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology” Camap drew his famous distinction between ‘internal’ and ‘external’ questions of existence, pronouncing the former meaningful and the latter meaningless. In The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism, Barry Stroud understands Carnap to be applying the verification criterion of meaningfulness in order to refute Cartesian skepticism. I suggest that Stroud misrepresents both Carnap's aim and method. Camap was responding to critics who suggested that his willingness to quantify over abstract entities in his work in semantics (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Readings in analytical philosophy.Hans Regnéll - 1971 - Stockholm,: Läromedelsförlagen.
    Empiricism, semantics, and ontology, by R. Carnap.--Decision and belief in science, by A. Wedberg.--On what there is, by W.V.O. Quine.--Metaphysics in logic, by G.J. Warnock.--Propositions, sentences, and the semantic definition of truth, by A. Pap.--Bertrand Russell's doubts about induction, by P. Edwards.--The logic of explanation, by C.G. Hempel and P. Oppenheim.--One's knowledge of other minds, by A.J. Ayer.--On the interpretation of philosophical texts, by G. Aspelin.--The Cartesian doubt and the Cogito, ergo sum, by K. Marc-Wogau.--Metaphysics, logic and theology, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Stroud’s Carnap.Marc Alspector-Kelly - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (2):276-302.
    In “Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology” Carnap drew his famous distinction between ‘internal’ and ‘external’ questions of existence, pronouncing the former meaningful and the latter meaningless. In The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism, Barry Stroud understands Carnap to be applying the verification criterion of meaningfulness in order to refute Cartesian skepticism. I suggest that Stroud misrepresents both Carnap’s aim and method. Carnap was responding to critics who suggested that his willingness to quantify over abstract entities in his work in semantics (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. The Unitarian Connection and Ricardo's Scientific Style.Sergio Volodia Marcello Cremaschi & Marcelo Dascal - 2002 - History of Political Economy 34 (2):505-508.
    We reply to Philippe Depoortère’s paper “On Ricardo’s method: The Unitarian influence examined. Some comments on Cremaschi and Dascal’s article ‘Malthus and Ricardo on Economic Methodology’”. Depoortère asks two questions: (1) was Ricardo’s ‘conversion’ to Unitarianism sincere? (2) did Ricardo follow the methodologies of Priestley and Belsham? His answers are that he was a ‘religious skeptic’ and he was not an ‘empiricist’ like Priestley and Belsham. We reply that the sincerity of Ricardo’s religious beliefs is irrelevant since we start with (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47. On Concepts and Ideas: Themes from G. W. Leibniz's New Essays.Lucia Oliveri - 2016 - In Christoph Kann David Hommen (ed.), Concepts and Categorization Systematic and Historical Perspectives. Münster, Germania: pp. 141-167.
    The topic of my paper is the virtual controversy between Leibniz and Lockeover concepts and ideas. At the end of the 17th century John Locke made a crucial contribution to semantics and philosophy: An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. The work represents a decisive turning point for the discussion about ideas and innatism. Indeed, Locke’s aim was to dismantle the Cartesian theory according to which ideas are innate in our soul. Against this onto-epistemological thesis, Locke maintains that all our knowledge (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. The Empirical Interpretation of French Cartesianism: the Académie des Sciences, the Journal des Sçavans and the Relationship with the Royal Society.Nausicaa Elena Milani - 2014 - Noctua 1 (2):312-480.
    The Système de philosophie by Pierre Sylvain Régis can be considered as the achievement both of the scientific liveliness of the Académie des Sciences in the 17th century and of its fruitful relationship with the Royal Society. Since it aims to shape the new conception of the universe in terms of a system, the Système represents one of the most mature achievements of Cartesian philosophy and it is characterized by an empirical interpretation of Descartes’ thought. The Système therefore reflects (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  37
    Kant’s Cognitive Semantics, Newton’s Rule Four of Philosophy and Scientific Realism.Kenneth R. Westphal - 2011 - Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain 63 (1-2):27-49.
    Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason contains an original and powerful semantics of singular cognitive reference which has important implications for epistemology and for philosophy of science. Here I argue that Kant’s semantics directly and strongly supports Newton’s Rule 4 of Philosophy in ways which support Newton’s realism about gravitational force. I begin with Newton’s Rule 4 of Philosophy and its role in Newton’s justification of realism about gravitational force (§2). Next I briefly summarize Kant’s semantics of singular cognitive reference (§3), (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  6
    I and my self.P. M. S. Hacker - 1990 - In Wittgenstein, meaning and mind. Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell. pp. 251–270.
    Contemporary debates about the role of the first‐person pronoun transpose onto a linguistic plane the discussion of the essential nature of a human being that stems from Cartesian metaphysics. Given the supposition that the word 'I' signifies a substance, it is perhaps understandable that Descartes had no qualms in using the expression “I”'. Hume's account earmarks the stalemate between rationalism and empiricism, as is evident in Reid's objection to the 'bundle theory': Whatever this self may be, it is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000